Sandbox
-
0:00 - 0:04[Music]
-
0:04 - 0:07Scientists often gather data through
-
0:07 - 0:11observation experiments, archival studies
-
0:11 - 0:14and so on. But they are rarely satisfied
-
0:14 - 0:18with data alone. Scientists want to draw
-
0:18 - 0:20conclusions from those data. They want to
-
0:20 - 0:22use the data to show that certain
-
0:22 - 0:25theories are right and others are wrong.
-
0:25 - 0:28To understand science, then, it will be
-
0:28 - 0:30important to understand when it is
-
0:30 - 0:32legitimate and when it is illegitimate
-
0:32 - 0:35to draw a specific conclusion from what
-
0:35 - 0:37we already know. We need to understand
-
0:37 - 0:43arguments; and that is why, in this
-
0:37 - 0:40the difference between good and bad
-
0:43 - 0:45lecture, we will take a look at logic--the
-
0:45 - 0:49study of argumentation. Let us first
-
0:49 - 0:53introduce some terminology. An argument
-
0:53 - 0:56consists of two parts: the premises and
-
0:56 - 0:59the conclusion. The premises are the
-
0:59 - 1:02things we presuppose and the conclusion
-
1:02 - 1:06is what we conclude from those premises.
-
1:06 - 1:08So let's look at an example:
-
1:08 - 1:12No medieval King had absolute power over
-
1:12 - 1:16his subjects. Louis 7 of France was a
-
1:16 - 1:21medieval King. So Louis 7 of France did
-
1:21 - 1:23not have absolute power over his
-
1:23 - 1:27subjects. Here the first two lines are
-
1:27 - 1:30the premises and a final line introduced
-
1:30 - 1:33by the word "so" is the conclusion. In this
-
1:33 - 1:36argument we assume that medieval kings
-
1:36 - 1:38did not have absolute power and that
-
1:38 - 1:41Louis 7 was a medieval King. And we
-
1:41 - 1:43conclude that he did not have absolute
-
1:43 - 1:47power. As a second piece of terminology
-
1:47 - 1:50we will make a distinction between valid
-
1:50 - 1:54and invalid arguments. A valid argument
-
1:54 - 1:56is an argument in which the conclusion
-
1:56 - 1:58really follows from the premises.
-
1:58 - 2:02Our example about Louis 7 is an example
-
2:02 - 2:04of a valid argument. The conclusion
-
2:04 - 2:07really follows from the premises. It
-
2:07 - 2:10makes sense to draw this conclusion from
-
2:10 - 2:13these premises.
-
2:13 - 2:16As an example of an invalid argument we
-
2:16 - 2:19can take this: No medieval King had
-
2:19 - 2:22absolute power over his subjects. Louis
-
2:22 - 2:25seven of France was a great horseman. So
-
2:25 - 2:28Louis seven of France did not have
-
2:28 - 2:32absolute power over his subjects. We just
-
2:32 - 2:34can't draw that conclusion from those
-
2:34 - 2:38premises. So this argument is not valid.
-
2:38 - 2:41It's invalid. Note that whether an
-
2:41 - 2:42argument is valid or not
-
2:42 - 2:44has nothing to do with whether the
-
2:44 - 2:47premises or the conclusions are true.
-
2:47 - 2:50Perhaps Louis 7 really was a great
-
2:50 - 2:52horseman. Then all the premises and the
-
2:52 - 2:54conclusion of that argument are true and
-
2:54 - 2:58yet the argument is invalid because the
-
2:58 - 3:01conclusion just doesn't follow from the
-
3:01 - 3:04premises. On the other hand it's also
-
3:04 - 3:07possible to have false premises and a
-
3:07 - 3:11valid argument. For instance: No medieval
-
3:11 - 3:12King had absolute power over his
-
3:12 - 3:15subjects. Victor Gijsbers was a
-
3:15 - 3:18medieval king. So Victor Gijsbers did not
-
3:18 - 3:20have absolute power over his subjects.
-
3:20 - 3:24This argument is perfectly valid even
-
3:24 - 3:26though the assumption that I am a
-
3:26 - 3:31medieval King is, as far as I know, false.
-
3:30 - 3:29We can now introduce our final piece of
-
3:30 - 3:35terminology: The distinction between two
-
3:36 - 3:39kinds of arguments. Deductive arguments
-
3:39 - 3:42and inductive arguments. A deductive
-
3:42 - 3:44argument is an argument in which the
-
3:44 - 3:46truth of the premises
-
3:46 - 3:49absolutely guarantee the truth of the
-
3:49 - 3:52conclusion. It's just not possible for
-
3:52 - 3:54the premises to be true and the
-
3:54 - 3:57conclusion to be false.
-
3:57 - 3:59Returning to our original example, we can
-
3:59 - 4:02see that this is a deductive argument. It
-
4:02 - 4:03is true
-
4:03 - 4:05the medieval Kings did not have absolute
-
4:05 - 4:08power; and if it is true that Louis 7 was
-
4:08 - 4:11a medieval King, then it must be true
-
4:11 - 4:13that he did not have absolute power.
-
4:13 - 4:16Or, in other words, if he did have
-
4:16 - 4:18absolute power then one of those two
-
4:18 - 4:23premises must be wrong. I'll come to the
-
4:23 - 4:24definition of inductive arguments in a
-
4:24 - 4:27moment, but first I want to point out two
-
4:27 - 4:29interesting features of deductive
-
4:29 - 4:33arguments: First, if you use deductive
-
4:33 - 4:36arguments you can't make any new
-
4:36 - 4:40mistakes. The only way for the conclusion
-
4:40 - 4:42of a deductive argument to be false is
-
4:42 - 4:46if one of your assumptions is false, so
-
4:46 - 4:48if you already believe something false
-
4:48 - 4:50then your conclusion may end up being
-
4:50 - 4:53false. But if your assumptions are true
-
4:53 - 4:57your conclusions are guaranteed to be
-
4:57 - 4:58true as well.
-
4:58 - 5:01So deductive arguments never introduce
-
5:01 - 5:04falsehoods if they weren't already there.
-
5:04 - 5:06And that makes them very strong and good
-
5:06 - 5:08arguments to use, because they're not
-
5:08 - 5:13very risky. Second, logicians found out
-
5:13 - 5:16already more than 2,000 years ago--and
-
5:16 - 5:18Aristotle played an important role here--
-
5:18 - 5:21that whether a deductive argument is
-
5:21 - 5:24valid or not can be determined just by
-
5:24 - 5:26looking at the form of the argument and
-
5:26 - 5:29ignoring its content. Even if you know
-
5:29 - 5:33nothing about medieval kings and Louis 7
-
5:33 - 5:35you can still see that our example
-
5:35 - 5:39argument is valid. How? Because there's
-
5:39 - 5:44this form: No A is B. C is A. So C is not B.
-
5:44 - 5:48Where A is "medieval King," B is "someone
-
5:48 - 5:51with absolute power," and C is "Louis 7" But
-
5:51 - 5:54we can put anything we like in the place
-
5:54 - 5:55of those letters and the argument will
-
5:55 - 5:58remain valid. For instance, let's choose A
-
5:58 - 6:02"Is a Dutchman" B "is humble" and C "is Victor
-
6:02 - 6:05or Gijsbers" Then we have: No Dutchman
-
6:05 - 6:07is humble. Victor Gijsbers is a
-
6:07 - 6:10Dutchman. So Victor Gijsbers is not
-
6:10 - 6:13humble. Which is another valid argument.
-
6:13 - 6:15Although of course the first premise is
-
6:15 - 6:19false and so is the conclusion. So we can
-
6:19 - 6:21see whether a deductive argument is
-
6:21 - 6:23valid simply by looking at its form
-
6:23 - 6:25without knowing anything about its
-
6:25 - 6:28content. And that is really important
-
6:28 - 6:30because that means that we can see
-
6:30 - 6:32whether something is a good argument
-
6:32 - 6:35without making any prior theoretical
-
6:35 - 6:38assumptions about the content matter. If
-
6:38 - 6:41we believe that scientists first
-
6:41 - 6:43collect data and then come to a
-
6:43 - 6:45conclusion about which theories are
-
6:45 - 6:47right and wrong, this is exactly what we
-
6:47 - 6:51would expect. We only need the data and
-
6:51 - 6:53some valid arguments which can be shown
-
6:53 - 6:56to be valid independent of any theories
-
6:56 - 6:59or ideas, and then we draw our
-
6:59 - 7:03conclusions. It would be great if science
-
7:03 - 7:08worked like that. Unfortunately, and I bet
-
7:08 - 7:10you saw that coming,
-
7:10 - 7:13science doesn't work like that. And it
-
7:13 - 7:15doesn't work like that because the most
-
7:15 - 7:17important arguments in science are not
-
7:17 - 7:22deductive. They are inductive. Remember
-
7:22 - 7:24that a deductive argument is an argument
-
7:24 - 7:26such that the truth of the premises
-
7:26 - 7:29absolutely guarantees the truth of the
-
7:29 - 7:33conclusion. An inductive argument is an
-
7:33 - 7:35argument where the truth of the premises
-
7:35 - 7:37gives good reason to believe the
-
7:37 - 7:40conclusion but does not absolutely
-
7:40 - 7:44guarantee its truth. Again let's look at
-
7:44 - 7:44an example:
-
7:44 - 7:47None of the medieval texts we have
-
7:47 - 7:49studied argues against the existence of
-
7:49 - 7:53God, so no scholar in the Middle Ages
-
7:53 - 7:56argued against the existence of God.
-
7:56 - 7:59That's a valid argument if it's true
-
7:59 - 8:01that none of the texts we have makes
-
8:01 - 8:03this argument, and we have a lot of texts,
-
8:03 - 8:06and it's quite plausible that nobody in
-
8:06 - 8:08that time actually made this argument.
-
8:08 - 8:12But it's indeed only plausible. It could
-
8:12 - 8:15be that the argument was made but
-
8:15 - 8:18somehow it wasn't transmitted to us. So
-
8:18 - 8:21in an inductive argument. The truth of
-
8:21 - 8:23the premises makes the conclusion likely,
-
8:23 - 8:27but it doesn't guarantee it. And that's
-
8:27 - 8:29generally the case in science. We have
-
8:29 - 8:31some limited data. We want to draw a
-
8:31 - 8:34general conclusion from those, and our
-
8:34 - 8:36data makes the conclusion likely but
-
8:36 - 8:42they don't make it certain. So, in science,
-
8:36 - 8:42we are continually making inductive
-
8:42 - 8:45arguments. And, as we will see in the next
-
8:45 - 8:48lecture, induction is a lot more
-
8:48 - 8:52problematic than deduction.
- Title:
- Sandbox
- Description:
-
You can use this Sandbox to try out things with the Amara tool.
The video that is primarily streaming here is http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ZU2kyr9jRkg , which is completely blank. But you can go to the URLs tab to add the URL of another video and make it primary.
Please remember to download your subtitles if you want to keep them, as they will get deleted - and the streaming URL reverted to the blank video if you changed it - after a week or two,
- Video Language:
- English
- Team:
- Captions Requested
- Duration:
- 01:46:39
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
koma edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
koma edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox |
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course