Sandbox
-
0:00 - 0:07[Music]
-
0:04 - 0:11Scientists often gather data through
-
0:07 - 0:14observation experiments, archival studies
-
0:11 - 0:18and so on. But they are rarely satisfied
-
0:14 - 0:20with data alone. Scientists want to draw
-
0:18 - 0:22conclusions from those data. They want to
-
0:20 - 0:25use the data to show that certain
-
0:22 - 0:28theories are right and others are wrong.
-
0:25 - 0:30To understand science, then, it will be
-
0:28 - 0:32important to understand when it is
-
0:30 - 0:35legitimate and when it is illegitimate.
-
0:32 - 0:38To draw a specific conclusion from what
-
0:35 - 0:40we already know we need to understand
-
0:38 - 0:43the difference between good and bad
-
0:40 - 0:45arguments; and that is why, in this
-
0:43 - 0:49lecture, we will take a look at logic--the
-
0:45 - 0:53study of argumentation. Let us first
-
0:49 - 0:56introduce some terminology. An argument
-
0:53 - 0:59consists of two parts: the premises and
-
0:56 - 1:02the conclusion. The premises are the
-
0:59 - 1:06things we presuppose and the conclusion
-
1:02 - 1:08is what we conclude from those premises.
-
1:06 - 1:12So let's look at an example:
-
1:08 - 1:16No medieval King had absolute power over
-
1:12 - 1:21his subjects. Louis 7 of France was a
-
1:16 - 1:23medieval King. So Louis 7 of France did
-
1:21 - 1:27not have absolute power over his
-
1:23 - 1:30subjects. Here the first two lines are
-
1:27 - 1:33the premises and a final line introduced
-
1:30 - 1:36by the word "so" is the conclusion. In this
-
1:33 - 1:38argument we assume that medieval kings
-
1:36 - 1:41did not have absolute power and that
-
1:38 - 1:43Louis 7 was a medieval King. And we
-
1:41 - 1:47conclude that he did not have absolute
-
1:43 - 1:50power. As a second piece of terminology
-
1:47 - 1:54we will make a distinction between valid
-
1:50 - 1:56and invalid arguments. A valid argument
-
1:54 - 1:58is an argument in which the conclusion
-
1:56 - 2:02really follows from the premises.
-
1:58 - 2:04Our example about Louis 7 is an example
-
2:02 - 2:07of a valid argument. The conclusion
-
2:04 - 2:10really follows from the premises. It
-
2:07 - 2:13makes sense to draw this conclusion from
-
2:10 - 2:16these premises.
-
2:13 - 2:19As an example of an invalid argument we
-
2:16 - 2:22can take this: No medieval King had
-
2:19 - 2:25absolute power over his subjects. Louis
-
2:22 - 2:28seven of France was a great horseman. So
-
2:25 - 2:32Louis seven of France did not have
-
2:28 - 2:35absolute power over his subjects. We just
-
2:32 - 2:38can't draw that conclusion from those
-
2:35 - 2:41premises. So this argument is not valid.
-
2:38 - 2:42It's invalid. Note that whether an
-
2:41 - 2:44argument is valid or not
-
2:42 - 2:47has nothing to do with whether the
-
2:44 - 2:50premises or the conclusions are true.
-
2:47 - 2:52Perhaps Louis 7 really was a great
-
2:50 - 2:54horseman. Then all the premises and the
-
2:52 - 2:58conclusion of that argument are true and
-
2:54 - 3:01yet the argument is invalid because the
-
2:58 - 3:04conclusion just doesn't follow from the
-
3:01 - 3:07premises. On the other hand it's also
-
3:04 - 3:11possible to have false premises and a
-
3:07 - 3:12valid argument. For instance: No medieval
-
3:11 - 3:15King had absolute power over his
-
3:12 - 3:18subjects. Victor Gijsbers was a
-
3:15 - 3:20medieval king. So Victor Gijsbers did not
-
3:18 - 3:24have absolute power over his subjects.
-
3:20 - 3:26This argument is perfectly valid even
-
3:24 - 3:30though the assumption that I am a
-
3:26 - 3:33medieval King is, as far as I know, false.
-
3:30 - 3:36We can now introduce our final piece of
-
3:33 - 3:39terminology: The distinction between two
-
3:36 - 3:42kinds of arguments. Deductive arguments
-
3:39 - 3:44and inductive arguments. A deductive
-
3:42 - 3:46argument is an argument in which the
-
3:44 - 3:49truth of the premises
-
3:46 - 3:52absolutely guarantee the truth of the
-
3:49 - 3:54conclusion. It's just not possible for
-
3:52 - 3:57the premises to be true and the
-
3:54 - 3:59conclusion to be false.
-
3:57 - 4:02Teturning to our original example, we can
-
3:59 - 4:03see that this is a deductive argument. It
-
4:02 - 4:05is true
-
4:03 - 4:08the medieval Kings did not have absolute
-
4:05 - 4:11power; and if it is true that Louis 7 was
-
4:08 - 4:13a medieval King, then it must be true
-
4:11 - 4:16that he did not have absolute power.
-
4:13 - 4:18Or, in other words, if he did have
-
4:16 - 4:23absolute power then one of those two
-
4:18 - 4:25premises must be wrong. I'll come to the
-
4:23 - 4:27definition of inductive arguments in a
-
4:25 - 4:29moment, but first I want to point out two
-
4:27 - 4:33interesting features of deductive
-
4:29 - 4:36arguments: First if you use deductive
-
4:33 - 4:40arguments you can't make any new
-
4:36 - 4:42mistakes. The only way for the conclusion
-
4:40 - 4:46of a deductive argument to be false is
-
4:42 - 4:48if one of your assumptions is false, so
-
4:46 - 4:50if you already believe something false
-
4:48 - 4:53then your conclusion may end up being
-
4:50 - 4:57false. But if your assumptions are true
-
4:53 - 4:58your conclusions are guaranteed to be
-
4:57 - 5:01true as well.
-
4:58 - 5:04So deductive arguments never introduce
-
5:01 - 5:06falsehoods if they weren't already there.
-
5:04 - 5:08And that makes them very strong and good
-
5:06 - 5:13arguments to use, because they're not
-
5:08 - 5:16very risky. Second logicians found out
-
5:13 - 5:18already more than 2,000 years ago--and
-
5:16 - 5:21Aristotle played an important role here--
-
5:18 - 5:24that whether a deductive argument is
-
5:21 - 5:26valid or not can be determined just by
-
5:24 - 5:29looking at the form of the argument and
-
5:26 - 5:33ignoring its content. Even if you know
-
5:29 - 5:35nothing about medieval kings and Louis 7
-
5:33 - 5:39you can still see that our example
-
5:35 - 5:45argument is valid. How? Because there's
-
5:39 - 5:48this form: No A is B. C is A. So C is not B.
-
5:45 - 5:52Where A is "medieval King," B is "someone
-
5:48 - 5:54with absolute power," and C is "Louis 7" But
-
5:52 - 5:55we can put anything we like in the place
-
5:54 - 5:58of those letters and the argument will
-
5:55 - 6:02remain valid. For instance, let's choose A
-
5:58 - 6:05"Is a Dutchman" B "is humble" and C "is Victor
-
6:02 - 6:07or Gijsbers" Then we have: No Dutchman
-
6:05 - 6:10is humble. Victor Gijsbers is a
-
6:07 - 6:13Dutchman. So Victor Gijsbers is not
-
6:10 - 6:15humble. Which is another valid argument.
-
6:13 - 6:19Although of course the first premise is
-
6:15 - 6:21false and so is the conclusion. So we can
-
6:19 - 6:23see whether a deductive argument is
-
6:21 - 6:25valid simply by looking at its form
-
6:23 - 6:28without knowing anything about its
-
6:25 - 6:30content. And that is really important
-
6:28 - 6:32because that means that we can see
-
6:30 - 6:35whether something is a good argument
-
6:32 - 6:38without making any prior theoretical
-
6:35 - 6:41assumptions about the content matter. If
-
6:38 - 6:43we believe that scientists first
-
6:41 - 6:45collect data and then come to a
-
6:43 - 6:47conclusion about which theories are
-
6:45 - 6:51right and wrong, this is exactly what we
-
6:47 - 6:53would expect. We only need the data and
-
6:51 - 6:56some valid arguments which can be shown
-
6:53 - 6:59to be valid independent of any theories
-
6:56 - 7:03or ideas, and then we draw our
-
6:59 - 7:08conclusions. It would be great if science
-
7:03 - 7:10worked like that. Unfortunately, and I bet
-
7:08 - 7:13you saw that coming,
-
7:10 - 7:15science doesn't work like that. And it
-
7:13 - 7:17doesn't work like that because the most
-
7:15 - 7:22important arguments in science are not
-
7:17 - 7:24deductive. They are inductive. Remember
-
7:22 - 7:26that a deductive argument is an argument
-
7:24 - 7:29such that the truth of the premises
-
7:26 - 7:33absolutely guarantees the truth of the
-
7:29 - 7:35conclusion. An inductive argument is an
-
7:33 - 7:37argument where the truth of the premises
-
7:35 - 7:40gives good reason to believe the
-
7:37 - 7:44conclusion but does not absolutely
-
7:40 - 7:44guarantee its truth. Again let's look at
-
7:44 - 7:47an example:
-
7:44 - 7:49None of the medieval texts we have
-
7:47 - 7:53studied argues against the existence of
-
7:49 - 7:56God, so no scholar in the Middle Ages
-
7:53 - 7:59argued against the existence of God.
-
7:56 - 8:01That's a valid argument if it's true
-
7:59 - 8:03that none of the texts we have makes
-
8:01 - 8:06this argument, and we have a lot of texts,
-
8:03 - 8:08and it's quite plausible that nobody in
-
8:06 - 8:12that time actually made this argument.
-
8:08 - 8:15But it's indeed only plausible. It could
-
8:12 - 8:18be that the argument was made but
-
8:15 - 8:21somehow it wasn't transmitted to us. So
-
8:18 - 8:23in an inductive argument. The truth of
-
8:21 - 8:27the premises makes the conclusion likely,
-
8:23 - 8:29but it doesn't guarantee it. And that's
-
8:27 - 8:32generally the case in science. We have
-
8:29 - 8:34some limited data. We want to draw a
-
8:32 - 8:37general conclusion from those, and our
-
8:34 - 8:39data makes the conclusion likely but
-
8:37 - 8:42they don't make it certain. So, in science,
-
8:39 - 8:45we are continually making inductive
-
8:42 - 8:48arguments. And, as we will see in the next
-
8:45 - 8:52lecture, induction is a lot more
-
8:48 - 8:52problematic than deduction.
- Title:
- Sandbox
- Description:
-
You can use this Sandbox to try out things with the Amara tool.
The video that is primarily streaming here is http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ZU2kyr9jRkg , which is completely blank. But you can go to the URLs tab to add the URL of another video and make it primary.
Please remember to download your subtitles if you want to keep them, as they will get deleted - and the streaming URL reverted to the blank video if you changed it - after a week or two,
- Video Language:
- English
- Team:
- Captions Requested
- Duration:
- 01:46:39
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
koma edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
koma edited English subtitles for Sandbox | ||
Claude Almansi edited English subtitles for Sandbox |
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course
Claude Almansi
Revision 1 = provided subtitles for Lecture 1.2 of Prof. Scott Plous' Social Psychology course