< Return to Video

Who decides what art means? - Hayley Levitt

  • Not Synced
    Imagine you and a friend are
    strolling through an art exhibit
  • Not Synced
    and a striking painting catches your eye.
  • Not Synced
    The vibrant red appears to you
    as a symbol of love,
  • Not Synced
    but your friend is convinced
    it's a symbol of war.
  • Not Synced
    And where you see stars in a romantic sky,
  • Not Synced
    your friend interprets global
    warming-inducing pollutants.
  • Not Synced
    To settle the debate, you turn to the
    internet, where you read
  • Not Synced
    that the painting is a replica of
    the artist's first-grade art project:
  • Not Synced
    Red was her favorite color
    and the silver dots are fairies.
  • Not Synced
    You now know the exact intentions
    that led to the creation of this work.
  • Not Synced
    Are you wrong to have enjoyed it
    as something the artist didn’t intend?
  • Not Synced
    Do you enjoy it less now
    that you know the truth?
  • Not Synced
    Just how much should
    the artist's intention
  • Not Synced
    affect your interpretation
    of the painting?
  • Not Synced
    It's a question that's been tossed around
  • Not Synced
    by philosophers and art critics for
    decades, with no consensus in sight.
  • Not Synced
    In the mid-20th century,
  • Not Synced
    literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and
    philosopher Monroe Beardsley
  • Not Synced
    argued that artistic
    intention was irrelevant.
  • Not Synced
    They called this the Intentional Fallacy:
  • Not Synced
    the belief that valuing an artist's
    intentions was misguided.
  • Not Synced
    Their argument was twofold:
  • Not Synced
    First, the artists we study are
    often no longer living,
  • Not Synced
    never recorded their intentions,
  • Not Synced
    or are simply unavailable to answer
    questions about their work.
  • Not Synced
    Second, even if there were a bounty
    of relevant information,
  • Not Synced
    Wimsatt and Beardsley believed
  • Not Synced
    it would distract us from the
    qualities of the work itself.
  • Not Synced
    They compared art to a dessert:
  • Not Synced
    When you taste a pudding,
  • Not Synced
    the chef's intentions don't affect whether
    you enjoy its flavor or texture.
  • Not Synced
    All that matters, they said,
    is that the pudding "works."
  • Not Synced
    Of course, what "works" for one person
    might not "work" for another.
  • Not Synced
    And since different interpretations
    appeal to different people,
  • Not Synced
    the silver dots in our painting could be
    reasonably interpreted as fairies,
  • Not Synced
    stars, or pollutants.
  • Not Synced
    By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the
    artist's interpretation of her own work
  • Not Synced
    would be just one among many equally
    acceptable possibilities.
  • Not Synced
    If you find this problematic,
  • Not Synced
    you might be more in line with Steven
    Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels,
  • Not Synced
    two literary theorists who rejected the
    Intentional Fallacy.
  • Not Synced
    They argued that an artist's
    intended meaning
  • Not Synced
    was not just one possible interpretation,
  • Not Synced
    but the only possible interpretation.
  • Not Synced
    For example, suppose you're
    walking along a beach
  • Not Synced
    and come across a series of marks in the
    sand that spell out a verse of poetry.
  • Not Synced
    Knapp and Michaels believed the
    poem would lose all meaning
  • Not Synced
    if you discovered these marks were not
    the work of a human being,
  • Not Synced
    but an odd coincidence
    produced by the waves.
  • Not Synced
    They believed an intentional creator
  • Not Synced
    is what makes the poem subject to
    understanding at all.
  • Not Synced
    Other thinkers advocate for
    a middle ground,
  • Not Synced
    suggesting that intention is just one
    piece in a larger puzzle.
  • Not Synced
    Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll
    took this stance,
  • Not Synced
    arguing that an artist's intentions are
    relevant to their audience
  • Not Synced
    the same way a speaker's intentions
  • Not Synced
    are relevant to the person they’re
    engaging in conversation.
  • Not Synced
    To understand how intentions function
    in conversation,
  • Not Synced
    Carroll said to imagine someone holding
    a cigarette and asking for a match.
  • Not Synced
    You respond by handing them a lighter,
  • Not Synced
    gathering that their motivation is to
    light their cigarette.
  • Not Synced
    The words they used to ask the question
    are important,
  • Not Synced
    but the intentions behind the question
    dictate your understanding and ultimately,
  • Not Synced
    your response.
  • Not Synced
    So which end of this spectrum
    do you lean towards?
  • Not Synced
    Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley,
    believe that when it comes to art,
  • Not Synced
    the proof should be in the pudding?
  • Not Synced
    Or do you think an artist's plans and
    motivations for their work
  • Not Synced
    affect its meaning?
  • Not Synced
    Artistic interpretation is a complex web
  • Not Synced
    that will probably never offer
    a definitive answer.
Title:
Who decides what art means? - Hayley Levitt
Speaker:
Hayley Levitt
Description:

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Team:
closed TED
Project:
TED-Ed
Duration:
04:21
Kayla Wolf edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf approved English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf accepted English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Tara Ahmadinejad edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Tara Ahmadinejad edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?

English subtitles

Revisions Compare revisions