1 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Imagine you and a friend are strolling through an art exhibit 2 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and a striking painting catches your eye. 3 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The vibrant red appears to you as a symbol of love, 4 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but your friend is convinced it's a symbol of war. 5 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And where you see stars in a romantic sky, 6 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 your friend interprets global warming-inducing pollutants. 7 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 To settle the debate, you turn to the internet, where you read 8 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that the painting is a replica of the artist's first-grade art project: 9 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Red was her favorite color and the silver dots are fairies. 10 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 You now know the exact intentions that led to the creation of this work. 11 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Are you wrong to have enjoyed it as something the artist didn’t intend? 12 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Do you enjoy it less now that you know the truth? 13 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Just how much should the artist's intention 14 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 affect your interpretation of the painting? 15 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's a question that's been tossed around 16 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 by philosophers and art critics for decades, with no consensus in sight. 17 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In the mid-20th century, 18 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and philosopher Monroe Beardsley 19 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 argued that artistic intention was irrelevant. 20 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They called this the Intentional Fallacy: 21 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the belief that valuing an artist's intentions was misguided. 22 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Their argument was twofold: 23 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 First, the artists we study are often no longer living, 24 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 never recorded their intentions, 25 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 or are simply unavailable to answer questions about their work. 26 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Second, even if there were a bounty of relevant information, 27 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Wimsatt and Beardsley believed 28 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 it would distract us from the qualities of the work itself. 29 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They compared art to a dessert: 30 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 When you taste a pudding, 31 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the chef's intentions don't affect whether you enjoy its flavor or texture. 32 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 All that matters, they said, is that the pudding "works." 33 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Of course, what "works" for one person might not "work" for another. 34 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And since different interpretations appeal to different people, 35 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the silver dots in our painting could be reasonably interpreted as fairies, 36 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 stars, or pollutants. 37 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the artist's interpretation of her own work 38 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 would be just one among many equally acceptable possibilities. 39 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 If you find this problematic, 40 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 you might be more in line with Steven Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels, 41 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 two literary theorists who rejected the Intentional Fallacy. 42 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They argued that an artist's intended meaning 43 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 was not just one possible interpretation, 44 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but the only possible interpretation. 45 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 For example, suppose you're walking along a beach 46 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and come across a series of marks in the sand that spell out a verse of poetry. 47 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Knapp and Michaels believed the poem would lose all meaning 48 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if you discovered these marks were not the work of a human being, 49 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but an odd coincidence produced by the waves. 50 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They believed an intentional creator 51 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is what makes the poem subject to understanding at all. 52 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Other thinkers advocate for a middle ground, 53 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 suggesting that intention is just one piece in a larger puzzle. 54 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll took this stance, 55 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 arguing that an artist's intentions are relevant to their audience 56 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the same way a speaker's intentions 57 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 are relevant to the person they’re engaging in conversation. 58 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 To understand how intentions function in conversation, 59 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Carroll said to imagine someone holding a cigarette and asking for a match. 60 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 You respond by handing them a lighter, 61 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 gathering that their motivation is to light their cigarette. 62 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The words they used to ask the question are important, 63 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but the intentions behind the question dictate your understanding and ultimately, 64 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 your response. 65 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So which end of this spectrum do you lean towards? 66 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley, believe that when it comes to art, 67 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the proof should be in the pudding? 68 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Or do you think an artist's plans and motivations for their work 69 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 affect its meaning? 70 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Artistic interpretation is a complex web 71 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that will probably never offer a definitive answer.