WEBVTT 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Imagine you and a friend are strolling through an art exhibit 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and a striking painting catches your eye. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 The vibrant red appears to you as a symbol of love, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but your friend is convinced it's a symbol of war. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 And where you see stars in a romantic sky, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 your friend interprets global warming-inducing pollutants. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 To settle the debate, you turn to the internet, where you read 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 that the painting is a replica of the artist's first-grade art project: 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Red was her favorite color and the silver dots are fairies. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 You now know the exact intentions that led to the creation of this work. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Are you wrong to have enjoyed it as something the artist didn’t intend? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Do you enjoy it less now that you know the truth? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Just how much should the artist's intention 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 affect your interpretation of the painting? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 It's a question that's been tossed around 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 by philosophers and art critics for decades, with no consensus in sight. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In the mid-20th century, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and philosopher Monroe Beardsley 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 argued that artistic intention was irrelevant. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They called this the Intentional Fallacy: 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the belief that valuing an artist's intentions was misguided. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Their argument was twofold: 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 First, the artists we study are often no longer living, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 never recorded their intentions, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 or are simply unavailable to answer questions about their work. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Second, even if there were a bounty of relevant information, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Wimsatt and Beardsley believed 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 it would distract us from the qualities of the work itself. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They compared art to a dessert: 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 When you taste a pudding, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the chef's intentions don't affect whether you enjoy its flavor or texture. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 All that matters, they said, is that the pudding "works." 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Of course, what "works" for one person might not "work" for another. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 And since different interpretations appeal to different people, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the silver dots in our painting could be reasonably interpreted as fairies, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 stars, or pollutants. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the artist's interpretation of her own work 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 would be just one among many equally acceptable possibilities. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 If you find this problematic, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 you might be more in line with Steven Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 two literary theorists who rejected the Intentional Fallacy. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They argued that an artist's intended meaning 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 was not just one possible interpretation, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but the only possible interpretation. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 For example, suppose you're walking along a beach 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and come across a series of marks in the sand that spell out a verse of poetry. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Knapp and Michaels believed the poem would lose all meaning 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 if you discovered these marks were not the work of a human being, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but an odd coincidence produced by the waves. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They believed an intentional creator 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 is what makes the poem subject to understanding at all. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Other thinkers advocate for a middle ground, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 suggesting that intention is just one piece in a larger puzzle. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll took this stance, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 arguing that an artist's intentions are relevant to their audience 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the same way a speaker's intentions 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 are relevant to the person they’re engaging in conversation. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 To understand how intentions function in conversation, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Carroll said to imagine someone holding a cigarette and asking for a match. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 You respond by handing them a lighter, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 gathering that their motivation is to light their cigarette. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 The words they used to ask the question are important, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but the intentions behind the question dictate your understanding and ultimately, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 your response. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 So which end of this spectrum do you lean towards? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley, believe that when it comes to art, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the proof should be in the pudding? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Or do you think an artist's plans and motivations for their work 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 affect its meaning? 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Artistic interpretation is a complex web 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 that will probably never offer a definitive answer.