9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Imagine you and a friend are [br]strolling through an art exhibit 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 and a striking painting catches your eye. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 The vibrant red appears to you [br]as a symbol of love, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 but your friend is convinced [br]it's a symbol of war. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 And where you see stars in a romantic sky, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 your friend interprets global [br]warming-inducing pollutants. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 To settle the debate, you turn to the[br]internet, where you read [br] 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 that the painting is a replica of [br]the artist's first-grade art project: 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Red was her favorite color [br]and the silver dots are fairies. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 You now know the exact intentions [br]that led to the creation of this work. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Are you wrong to have enjoyed it [br]as something the artist didn’t intend? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Do you enjoy it less now [br]that you know the truth? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Just how much should [br]the artist's intention 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 affect your interpretation [br]of the painting? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 It's a question that's been tossed around 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 by philosophers and art critics for [br]decades, with no consensus in sight. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 In the mid-20th century, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and [br]philosopher Monroe Beardsley 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 argued that artistic [br]intention was irrelevant. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 They called this the Intentional Fallacy: 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 the belief that valuing an artist's [br]intentions was misguided. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Their argument was twofold: 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 First, the artists we study are [br]often no longer living, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 never recorded their intentions, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 or are simply unavailable to answer [br]questions about their work. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Second, even if there were a bounty [br]of relevant information, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Wimsatt and Beardsley believed 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 it would distract us from the [br]qualities of the work itself. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 They compared art to a dessert: 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 When you taste a pudding, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 the chef's intentions don't affect whether[br]you enjoy its flavor or texture. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 All that matters, they said, [br]is that the pudding "works." 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Of course, what "works" for one person [br]might not "work" for another. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 And since different interpretations [br]appeal to different people, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 the silver dots in our painting could be [br]reasonably interpreted as fairies, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 stars, or pollutants. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the[br]artist's interpretation of her own work 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 would be just one among many equally[br]acceptable possibilities. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 If you find this problematic, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 you might be more in line with Steven [br]Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 two literary theorists who rejected the[br]Intentional Fallacy. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 They argued that an artist's [br]intended meaning 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 was not just one possible interpretation, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 but the only possible interpretation. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 For example, suppose you're [br]walking along a beach 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 and come across a series of marks in the [br]sand that spell out a verse of poetry. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Knapp and Michaels believed the [br]poem would lose all meaning 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 if you discovered these marks were not [br]the work of a human being, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 but an odd coincidence [br]produced by the waves. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 They believed an intentional creator 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 is what makes the poem subject to [br]understanding at all. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Other thinkers advocate for [br]a middle ground, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 suggesting that intention is just one [br]piece in a larger puzzle. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll [br]took this stance, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 arguing that an artist's intentions are [br]relevant to their audience 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 the same way a speaker's intentions 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 are relevant to the person they’re [br]engaging in conversation. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 To understand how intentions function [br]in conversation, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Carroll said to imagine someone holding[br]a cigarette and asking for a match. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 You respond by handing them a lighter, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 gathering that their motivation is to [br]light their cigarette. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 The words they used to ask the question [br]are important, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 but the intentions behind the question [br]dictate your understanding and ultimately, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 your response. 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 So which end of this spectrum [br]do you lean towards? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley, [br]believe that when it comes to art, 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 the proof should be in the pudding? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Or do you think an artist's plans and [br]motivations for their work 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 affect its meaning? 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 Artistic interpretation is a complex web 9:59:59.000,9:59:59.000 that will probably never offer [br]a definitive answer.