< Return to Video

The dark side of free will | Gregg Caruso | TEDxChemungRiver

  • 0:10 - 0:14
    I have been thinking a lot lately
    about the following question:
  • 0:14 - 0:17
    what would happen
    if we came to disbelieve in free will?
  • 0:17 - 0:20
    What would this mean
    for our interpersonal relationships,
  • 0:20 - 0:22
    society, morality, meaning in the law?
  • 0:22 - 0:26
    For example, would giving up the belief
    in free will have dire consequences
  • 0:26 - 0:28
    for society or something?
  • 0:28 - 0:30
    Or would it rather have
    a humanizing effect
  • 0:30 - 0:32
    on our practices and polices,
  • 0:32 - 0:35
    freeing us from the negative effects
    of belief in free will?
  • 0:35 - 0:37
    What I would like to propose today
  • 0:37 - 0:40
    is that the belief in free will
    rather than being a good thing
  • 0:40 - 0:43
    actually has a dark side
    and that we'd be better off without it.
  • 0:43 - 0:45
    I know this is counterintuitive.
  • 0:45 - 0:48
    Many people fear that life
    without free will lead to nihilism,
  • 0:48 - 0:51
    there'd be no reason to go on,
    or that it would undermine morality.
  • 0:51 - 0:54
    Or that we will just let
    criminals run free
  • 0:54 - 0:57
    since there'd be no moral responsibility.
  • 0:57 - 0:59
    But I would like to paint
    a different picture for you today.
  • 0:59 - 1:02
    It begins with the idea
    of free will skepticism.
  • 1:02 - 1:05
    So I am a free will skeptic.
    I deny the existence of free will.
  • 1:05 - 1:08
    Free will skeptics maintain
    that who we are, what we do,
  • 1:08 - 1:11
    is ultimately the result of factors
    beyond our control,
  • 1:11 - 1:13
    and because of this,
  • 1:13 - 1:16
    we are never morally responsible for
    our actions in the basic desert sense
  • 1:16 - 1:21
    that is the sense that would make us
    truly deserving of praise and blame.
  • 1:21 - 1:25
    Historically, there have been a number
    of philosophical and scientific arguments
  • 1:25 - 1:26
    for free will skepticism,
  • 1:26 - 1:29
    and I've promoted
    these arguments in my own work,
  • 1:29 - 1:32
    but I'm not here today to try
    to convince you that you lack free will.
  • 1:32 - 1:34
    It's not my goal.
  • 1:34 - 1:37
    I'm actually interested
    in a slightly different question:
  • 1:37 - 1:39
    what would happen if we came
    to accept this perspective?
  • 1:39 - 1:43
    What would happen, practically speaking,
    if we came to disbelieve in free will?
  • 1:43 - 1:46
    Would it be, on the whole,
    a good thing or a bad thing?
  • 1:46 - 1:48
    And it's here that I'm an optimist.
  • 1:48 - 1:51
    I am optimistic about the prospects
    of life without free will.
  • 1:51 - 1:53
    I call myself an optimistic skeptic.
  • 1:53 - 1:56
    As an optimistic skeptic,
  • 1:56 - 1:58
    I maintain that life without free will
  • 1:58 - 2:00
    is not only possible
    but that it's preferable.
  • 2:00 - 2:02
    Prospects of finding meaning in life
  • 2:02 - 2:05
    and sustaining good interpersonal
    relationships, for example,
  • 2:05 - 2:06
    would not be threatened.
  • 2:06 - 2:08
    Although certain systems of punishment
  • 2:08 - 2:11
    like those based on the model
    of retribution or just deserts
  • 2:11 - 2:12
    would be ruled out;
  • 2:12 - 2:16
    preventive detention and rehabilitation
    programs would still be justified.
  • 2:16 - 2:18
    I will say a little bit more
    about these in a moment.
  • 2:18 - 2:20
    So as an optimistic skeptic,
  • 2:20 - 2:25
    I maintain that life without free will
    may actually be good for our well being,
  • 2:25 - 2:26
    and our relationships with others,
  • 2:26 - 2:30
    since it could tend to eradicate
    an often destructive form of moral anger,
  • 2:30 - 2:31
    a kind of moral anger
  • 2:31 - 2:35
    that's corrosive to our relationships
    and to our social policies.
  • 2:35 - 2:39
    So to better understand
    the dark side of free will,
  • 2:39 - 2:41
    what I want to do is just talk about
  • 2:41 - 2:44
    some recent empirical work
    in moral political physiology.
  • 2:44 - 2:47
    What this work has done has actually shown
  • 2:47 - 2:51
    that there is a number of interesting
    and potentially troubling correlations
  • 2:51 - 2:52
    between the belief in free will
  • 2:52 - 2:55
    and people's other moral religious
    and political beliefs.
  • 2:55 - 2:58
    In particular, what they found is
    that free will beliefs are correlated
  • 2:58 - 3:02
    with higher levels
    of religiosity, punitiveness,
  • 3:02 - 3:04
    and a number of conservative
    beliefs in attitude,
  • 3:04 - 3:07
    such as just world belief
    and right wing authoritarianism.
  • 3:07 - 3:09
    I am only going to focus on
    two of these today,
  • 3:09 - 3:13
    that is the connection between the belief
    in free will and punitiveness,
  • 3:13 - 3:16
    and that between the belief in free will
    and what's called just world belief.
  • 3:16 - 3:19
    So we take punitiveness for example.
  • 3:19 - 3:22
    What this research has shown is
    that where believe in free will is strong,
  • 3:22 - 3:24
    as we see increased punitiveness,
  • 3:24 - 3:27
    that is people are more likely to call
    for harsher forms of punishment
  • 3:27 - 3:29
    in a number of different scenarios.
  • 3:29 - 3:32
    And this makes sense:
    if you think people possess free will,
  • 3:32 - 3:36
    then you believe they justly deserve to
    be praised and blamed for their actions.
  • 3:36 - 3:40
    if they engage in an immoral act, you want
    to see them get their just deserts, right?
  • 3:40 - 3:42
    It's very close
    to a notion of retribution:
  • 3:42 - 3:46
    you want to inflict harm on them
    for the harm they've inflicted on others.
  • 3:46 - 3:49
    But the downside of this is, again,
    you can create a moral anger
  • 3:49 - 3:53
    that's destructive to our relationships
    with others and to our social policies.
  • 3:53 - 3:56
    So consider this on a macro level,
  • 3:56 - 4:00
    belief in free will is relatively strong
    in the United States.
  • 4:00 - 4:02
    In fact, it's built right
    into the mythology
  • 4:02 - 4:05
    of the rugged individual,
    the self-made man, the causa Sui,
  • 4:05 - 4:08
    the person that can pull themselves up
    from the bootstraps
  • 4:08 - 4:10
    and overcome all
    of their life circumstances.
  • 4:10 - 4:12
    But because we are
    so committed to this belief,
  • 4:12 - 4:15
    we are also a relatively punitive society.
  • 4:15 - 4:17
    Consider this one simple fact:
  • 4:17 - 4:20
    the United States makes up about 5%
    of the world's population,
  • 4:20 - 4:24
    yet it incarcerates
    25% of the world's prisoners.
  • 4:24 - 4:27
    I will say that again
    because it's a rather startling statistic:
  • 4:27 - 4:30
    we make up a relatively small sliver
    of the world's population, about 5%,
  • 4:30 - 4:34
    but we house and imprison
    25% of the world's prisoners.
  • 4:34 - 4:38
    I don't think it's controversial to say
    our criminal justice system is broken.
  • 4:38 - 4:42
    It is not working, not making us safer,
    it's not reducing crime,
  • 4:42 - 4:44
    it's, by no means, achieving
    our desired social goals,
  • 4:44 - 4:48
    and it is not reducing the rate
    of recidivism, that is repeat crime.
  • 4:48 - 4:51
    But just perhaps, if we adopt
    the skeptical perspective,
  • 4:51 - 4:56
    we might be able to adopt more effective,
    and more humane policies.
  • 4:56 - 4:58
    So let me just briefly sketch quickly
  • 4:58 - 5:01
    how a free will skeptic
    might address criminal behavior.
  • 5:01 - 5:04
    There's a professor
    - not too far from here,
  • 5:04 - 5:06
    his name is Derek Pereboom,
    he teaches at Cornell University;
  • 5:06 - 5:08
    he's a free will skeptic, like myself -
  • 5:08 - 5:11
    and he proposes a model
    for dealing with dangerous criminals
  • 5:11 - 5:14
    based on analogy with quarantine.
  • 5:14 - 5:18
    So people who contract contagious diseases
    do so for no fault of their own,
  • 5:18 - 5:21
    they're not morally responsible
    for having done so;
  • 5:21 - 5:23
    we don't think they
    deserve to be punished.
  • 5:23 - 5:24
    But we do feel justified
  • 5:24 - 5:27
    in quarantining those individuals
    for the safety of society.
  • 5:27 - 5:30
    Well, we can say the same thing
    for dangerous criminals
  • 5:30 - 5:33
    that is even you adopted
    the perspective that I am advocating,
  • 5:33 - 5:36
    and you believe that individuals
    are not ultimately responsible
  • 5:36 - 5:37
    for becoming who they are,
  • 5:37 - 5:41
    we could still justify detaining those
    individuals for the safety of society.
  • 5:41 - 5:44
    But if we did this, this would entail
    a number of major reforms,
  • 5:44 - 5:48
    all of which I think are actually
    really important and good.
  • 5:48 - 5:49
    For one, we'd have the duty
  • 5:49 - 5:52
    to the well-being
    and rehabilitation of criminals,
  • 5:52 - 5:54
    just like you would have a duty
  • 5:54 - 5:56
    to treat the person
    in quarantine for their disease.
  • 5:56 - 5:59
    Secondly,
  • 6:03 - 6:06
    you couldn't treat those individuals
    cruelly while being detained,
  • 6:06 - 6:10
    just like you couldn't treat cruelly
    the people we are holding in quarantine.
  • 6:10 - 6:13
    Thirdly, if there are less severe
    forms of punishment available,
  • 6:13 - 6:16
    we'd have to opt for
    those less severe forms of punishment
  • 6:16 - 6:19
    and that might entail rethinking
    some of our harsher sentencing laws,
  • 6:19 - 6:23
    and some of our crueler forms
    of punishment in super max prisons.
  • 6:23 - 6:24
    And lastly,
  • 6:24 - 6:27
    if you are someone like myself,
    you think it's the causal circumstances
  • 6:27 - 6:29
    that drive these behaviors
    in the first place,
  • 6:29 - 6:33
    then free will skeptics would put
    their money, resources and focus
  • 6:33 - 6:35
    on addressing the systemic causes
    that lead to criminality:
  • 6:35 - 6:37
    wealth, inequality, educational inequity.
  • 6:37 - 6:40
    So instead of blaming people
    and punishing them,
  • 6:40 - 6:43
    on the tail-end, you'd try to prevent
    the criminal behavior in the first place.
  • 6:43 - 6:45
    (Applause)
  • 6:45 - 6:46
    Thank you.
  • 6:46 - 6:51
    Not only do I think free will skeptics can
    deal successfully with criminal behaviors,
  • 6:51 - 6:53
    I think they could do so
    more humanely and more effectively.
  • 6:53 - 6:56
    So let me switch over
    to the other belief I mentioned:
  • 6:56 - 6:59
    belief in free will has also been shown
    through this research
  • 6:59 - 7:01
    to correlate with what is known
    as just world belief.
  • 7:01 - 7:03
    So what is it?
  • 7:03 - 7:05
    Fundamentally, it is the belief
    that the world is just,
  • 7:05 - 7:09
    good things happen to good people,
    and bad things happen to bad people.
  • 7:09 - 7:12
    But also, fundamentally,
    it's a blame-the-victim approach
  • 7:12 - 7:15
    since it maintains that individuals
    justly deserve what they get,
  • 7:15 - 7:19
    and that those who meet misfortune
    have often brought it them on themselves.
  • 7:19 - 7:24
    In the 1960s, psychologists developed
    what is known as just world belief scale.
  • 7:24 - 7:27
    It was meant to design people's commitment
    to this type of belief,
  • 7:27 - 7:31
    but it was also particularly designed to
    capture the natural tendency people have
  • 7:31 - 7:34
    to blame those who meet misfortune
    for their own circumstances.
  • 7:34 - 7:39
    Over the years, what they found
    is that high scores on this belief,
  • 7:39 - 7:42
    correlate with the likelihood
    of derogating innocent victims,
  • 7:42 - 7:45
    trusting current institutions
    and authorities,
  • 7:45 - 7:48
    and blaming the poor and praising
    the rich for their respective faiths.
  • 7:48 - 7:51
    As I said, this is essentially
    a blame-the-victim approach;
  • 7:51 - 7:54
    you can see manifestations
    of it all throughout society.
  • 7:54 - 7:55
    One of the more pernicious
  • 7:55 - 7:58
    is the tendency, both among
    ordinary folk and the legal system,
  • 7:58 - 8:01
    to blame rape victims
    for their own circumstances.
  • 8:01 - 8:02
    So if the world is just,
  • 8:02 - 8:06
    and good things happen to good people,
    and bad things happen to bad people,
  • 8:06 - 8:08
    to try to reconcile
    such a horrific act as rape
  • 8:08 - 8:11
    while preserving the belief
    that the world is just,
  • 8:11 - 8:14
    you turn that innocent victim
    into somebody that's guilty.
  • 8:14 - 8:15
    They were dressed provocatively,
  • 8:15 - 8:18
    they were walking
    where they shouldn't had been walking.
  • 8:18 - 8:21
    Another manifestation
    of this blame-the-victim approach
  • 8:21 - 8:22
    could be seen throughout society.
  • 8:22 - 8:25
    For example, blaming those in poverty
    for their own circumstances.
  • 8:25 - 8:28
    Claiming that those on welfare
    are lazy or mooches.
  • 8:28 - 8:31
    Or blaming educational inequity on
    the children and the parents themselves.
  • 8:31 - 8:35
    But we all know, at least on a more
    rational deliberate moment,
  • 8:35 - 8:36
    that the world is not just,
  • 8:36 - 8:39
    and that the lottery of life
    is not always fair.
  • 8:39 - 8:42
    We need to acknowledge the role
    that luck plays in our lives,
  • 8:42 - 8:44
    who we are, and how we turn out, right?
  • 8:44 - 8:47
    We don't all have equal starting points.
  • 8:47 - 8:49
    As I said in the beginning,
    I'm an optimist,
  • 8:49 - 8:53
    I am optimistic that if we could adopt
    this skeptical perspective,
  • 8:53 - 8:54
    we may be able to free ourselves
  • 8:54 - 8:57
    from some of these beliefs
    and harmful tendencies.
  • 8:57 - 8:59
    In fact, there was
    a recent study that came out
  • 8:59 - 9:01
    in the Journal of Psychological Science
  • 9:01 - 9:04
    that found that by reducing
    people's beliefs in free will,
  • 9:04 - 9:05
    it actually made them less punitive,
  • 9:05 - 9:09
    and call for less harsh forms of treatment
    in a number of hypothetical scenarios.
  • 9:09 - 9:13
    This tells me two things: one,
    it reaffirms what I was saying earlier,
  • 9:13 - 9:16
    that where believe in free will is strong
    as we see increased punitiveness,
  • 9:16 - 9:18
    but it also provides hopes to me
  • 9:18 - 9:22
    that we can perhaps relinquish ourselves
    on some of these more harmful beliefs
  • 9:22 - 9:25
    and by doing so, loose some
    of that moral anger I've been discussing.
  • 9:25 - 9:27
    So my proposal is rather simple.
  • 9:27 - 9:30
    Let's not fear free will skepticism.
    Let's embrace it.
  • 9:30 - 9:33
    Let's give up the belief
    in free will, and with it,
  • 9:33 - 9:37
    the pernicious belief in just-deserts,
    that people justly deserve what they get.
  • 9:37 - 9:39
    Let's leave this adequate notion behind,
  • 9:39 - 9:41
    lose our moral anger
    and stop blaming the victim.
  • 9:41 - 9:44
    Instead, let's turn our attention
    to the difficult task
  • 9:44 - 9:46
    of addressing the causes that lead
  • 9:46 - 9:50
    to criminality, to wealth inequity,
    and educational inequity.
  • 9:50 - 9:53
    Once we relinquish the belief
    in free will, this will allow us
  • 9:53 - 9:56
    to look more clearly at the causes
    and more deeply at the systems
  • 9:56 - 9:58
    that shape individuals and their behavior,
  • 9:58 - 10:01
    and this will allow us to adopt
    more humane and more effective policies
  • 10:01 - 10:04
    in education, criminal justice,
    and social policies.
  • 10:04 - 10:05
    Thank you very much.
  • 10:05 - 10:06
    (Applause)
Title:
The dark side of free will | Gregg Caruso | TEDxChemungRiver
Description:

This talk was given at a local TEDx event, produced independently of the TED Conferences.

What would happen if we all believed free will didn't exist? As a free will skeptic, Dr. Gregg Caruso contends our society would be better off believing there is no such thing as free will.

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Team:
closed TED
Project:
TEDxTalks
Duration:
10:12

English subtitles

Revisions