< Return to Video

Critical Thinking Fundamentals: Introduction to Critical Thinking

  • 0:00 - 0:04
    (intro music)
  • 0:06 - 0:07
    I'm Geoff Pynn. I teach at
  • 0:07 - 0:09
    Northern Illinois University,
  • 0:09 - 0:13
    and this is an introduction
    to critical thinking.
  • 0:13 - 0:16
    In this lesson, we're gonna
    talk about three things.
  • 0:17 - 0:20
    First, what is critical thinking?
  • 0:20 - 0:23
    Second, what is an argument?
  • 0:23 - 0:25
    And third, what's the difference between
  • 0:25 - 0:28
    deductive and ampliative arguments?
  • 0:29 - 0:31
    Okay, so what is critical thinking?
  • 0:31 - 0:33
    Well, fundamentally, critical thinking
  • 0:33 - 0:35
    is about making sure that you have
  • 0:35 - 0:37
    good reasons for your beliefs.
  • 0:37 - 0:38
    What does that mean?
  • 0:38 - 0:40
    So suppose that you and your friend
  • 0:40 - 0:43
    are talking about who's
    gonna be at tonight's party.
  • 0:43 - 0:46
    And she says to you, quite confidently,
  • 0:46 - 0:48
    "Monty won't be at the party."
  • 0:48 - 0:50
    You're not sure whether
    or not to believe her,
  • 0:50 - 0:51
    so it would be natural
    for you to follow up
  • 0:51 - 0:54
    by asking, "Why do you think so?"
  • 0:54 - 0:55
    And there are a lot of different things
  • 0:55 - 0:57
    that she might say in response.
  • 0:57 - 0:58
    We're gonna talk about three
  • 0:58 - 1:01
    possible answers she could give.
  • 1:01 - 1:03
    First, she might say, "I can't stand him,
  • 1:03 - 1:05
    and I want to have a good time."
  • 1:06 - 1:08
    Second, she might say,
    "Well, he's really shy,
  • 1:08 - 1:11
    and he rarely goes to parties."
  • 1:11 - 1:12
    And third, she might say,
  • 1:12 - 1:14
    "He's in Beijing, and it's impossible
  • 1:14 - 1:17
    to get here from
    Beijing in an afternoon."
  • 1:17 - 1:19
    The first response that she gives you
  • 1:19 - 1:21
    does not give you a good reason to believe
  • 1:21 - 1:23
    that Monty won't be at the party.
  • 1:23 - 1:25
    The second reason,
    though, is a good reason
  • 1:25 - 1:28
    to believe that Monty
    won't be at the party.
  • 1:28 - 1:30
    If he's really shy and
    rarely goes to parties,
  • 1:30 - 1:33
    then it's probable that he
    won't be at tonight's party.
  • 1:33 - 1:35
    Similarly, the third reason
    also gives you a good
  • 1:35 - 1:38
    reason to believe that
    Monty won't be at the party.
  • 1:38 - 1:40
    If he's in Beijing, and
    it's impossible to get here
  • 1:40 - 1:43
    from Beijing in an afternoon,
    then it's guaranteed
  • 1:43 - 1:45
    that he won't be at the party.
  • 1:45 - 1:46
    And when you notice things like that,
  • 1:46 - 1:47
    when you distinguish between good
  • 1:47 - 1:50
    and bad reasons for believing something,
  • 1:50 - 1:52
    you're exercising your
    critical thinking skills.
  • 1:54 - 1:55
    So critical thinking is making sure
  • 1:55 - 1:57
    we have good reasons for our beliefs,
  • 1:57 - 1:59
    and so one of the essential
    skills that you learn
  • 1:59 - 2:01
    when you're studying
    critical thinking is how
  • 2:01 - 2:04
    to distinguish good reasons
    for believing something
  • 2:04 - 2:07
    from bad reasons for believing something.
  • 2:07 - 2:08
    Now, it's worth saying something about
  • 2:08 - 2:10
    how I'm using the term "good" here.
  • 2:10 - 2:12
    I'm not using it to indicate anything
  • 2:12 - 2:14
    having to do with morality or ethics.
  • 2:14 - 2:17
    So it's not morally right or morally good
  • 2:17 - 2:20
    to believe something on
    the basis of good reasons.
  • 2:20 - 2:22
    Similarly, it's not morally
    wrong, or evil, or wicked
  • 2:22 - 2:25
    to believe something on
    the basis of a bad reason.
  • 2:25 - 2:28
    Rather, here, what it is to
    say that a reason is good
  • 2:28 - 2:31
    is closely tied to the notion of truth.
  • 2:31 - 2:32
    So a good reason for a belief is one
  • 2:32 - 2:35
    that makes it probable, that is, it's one
  • 2:35 - 2:37
    that makes the belief likely to be true.
  • 2:37 - 2:39
    The very best reasons for a belief
  • 2:39 - 2:42
    make it certain, they guarantee it.
  • 2:42 - 2:44
    So why does this matter?
  • 2:44 - 2:45
    Well, the reason that critical thinking
  • 2:45 - 2:47
    is important is because,
    since we're rational,
  • 2:47 - 2:49
    we want our beliefs to be true.
  • 2:49 - 2:52
    Rational people want to have true beliefs,
  • 2:52 - 2:54
    and they want not to have false beliefs.
  • 2:54 - 2:57
    And the best way to be
    rational in this way
  • 2:57 - 2:59
    is to form beliefs only when you
  • 2:59 - 3:01
    find good reasons for them.
  • 3:01 - 3:03
    Okay, that leads us to
    our second question:
  • 3:03 - 3:05
    What is an argument?
  • 3:05 - 3:08
    Well, an argument is a set
    of statements that together
  • 3:08 - 3:11
    comprise a reason for a further statement.
  • 3:11 - 3:13
    So, for example, we can consider one
  • 3:13 - 3:18
    of your friend's responses
    before as an argument.
  • 3:18 - 3:20
    She's given you two statements,
  • 3:20 - 3:23
    "Monty's really shy" and
    "Monty rarely goes to parties,"
  • 3:23 - 3:24
    which together comprise
    a reason for believing
  • 3:24 - 3:27
    that Monty won't be at the party.
  • 3:27 - 3:29
    The statements that are the reason,
  • 3:29 - 3:31
    we call the argument's premises.
  • 3:31 - 3:33
    So "Monty's really shy" is premise one,
  • 3:33 - 3:36
    "Monty rarely goes to
    parties" is premise two,
  • 3:36 - 3:38
    and the statement that
    those premises give you
  • 3:38 - 3:41
    reason to believe, we call
    the argument's conclusion.
  • 3:43 - 3:45
    A good argument is one
    in which the premises
  • 3:45 - 3:48
    give you a good reason for
    the conclusion, that is,
  • 3:48 - 3:51
    the premises make the
    conclusion likely to be true.
  • 3:51 - 3:52
    In that case, we say that the argument
  • 3:52 - 3:55
    supports the conclusion.
  • 3:55 - 3:57
    Good arguments support their conclusions,
  • 3:57 - 4:01
    and bad arguments don't
    support their conclusions.
  • 4:01 - 4:03
    So a key part of critical
    thinking is learning
  • 4:03 - 4:05
    to evaluate arguments to determine
  • 4:05 - 4:07
    whether or not they're good or bad,
  • 4:07 - 4:08
    that is, whether or not their premises
  • 4:08 - 4:10
    support their conclusions.
  • 4:11 - 4:14
    The red argument is the first response
  • 4:14 - 4:15
    that she gave, two premises,
  • 4:15 - 4:18
    "I can't stand Monty" and "I
    want to have a good time."
  • 4:18 - 4:21
    And the conclusion is "Monty
    won't be at the party."
  • 4:21 - 4:23
    And the third argument,
    which we'll put in purple,
  • 4:23 - 4:25
    consisted also of two premises,
  • 4:25 - 4:27
    "Monty's in Beijing" and
    "He can't get from Beijing
  • 4:27 - 4:30
    to the party in time, so
    he won't be at the party."
  • 4:31 - 4:34
    Now, as I indicated
    before, the first argument
  • 4:34 - 4:37
    is not good, while the
    purple argument is good.
  • 4:40 - 4:42
    And here I can explain a
    little bit more about why.
  • 4:42 - 4:46
    If you consider what the
    red argument's premises say,
  • 4:46 - 4:47
    that your friend can't stand Monty,
  • 4:47 - 4:49
    and she wants to have a good time,
  • 4:49 - 4:50
    and think about their relationship
  • 4:50 - 4:52
    to the conclusion of the argument,
  • 4:52 - 4:54
    you'll see that those
    statements don't make
  • 4:54 - 4:57
    that conclusion any
    more likely to be true.
  • 4:57 - 4:58
    The fact that your
    friend can't stand Monty
  • 4:58 - 5:00
    and wants to have a good
    time doesn't do anything
  • 5:00 - 5:03
    to make it more likely
    that Monty won't be there.
  • 5:03 - 5:06
    It's simply unrelated to the conclusion.
  • 5:06 - 5:07
    In the purple argument,
    though, the premises,
  • 5:07 - 5:11
    if they're true, they guarantee
    the conclusion is true.
  • 5:11 - 5:13
    So they make it very probable.
  • 5:13 - 5:15
    The truth of the premises
    guarantees the truth
  • 5:15 - 5:17
    of the conclusion, and so
    in the purple argument,
  • 5:17 - 5:20
    the premises do support the conclusion.
  • 5:20 - 5:22
    Now, it's worth pointing
    out that the red argument,
  • 5:22 - 5:24
    though it's bad as it
    stands, could be made
  • 5:24 - 5:26
    a good argument with the addition
  • 5:26 - 5:28
    of some background premise.
  • 5:28 - 5:30
    So, for example, if you found out
  • 5:30 - 5:32
    that your friend was
    the person who decided
  • 5:32 - 5:34
    who was going to be invited to the party,
  • 5:34 - 5:36
    then the fact that she can't stand Monty
  • 5:36 - 5:37
    and wants to have a good time
  • 5:37 - 5:38
    would give you a good reason to believe
  • 5:38 - 5:40
    that Monty won't be at the party,
  • 5:40 - 5:41
    because it would give you reason
  • 5:41 - 5:44
    to believe that she didn't invite him.
  • 5:44 - 5:46
    But as it stands, the
    argument is not good.
  • 5:46 - 5:48
    Those two premises
    considered in themselves
  • 5:48 - 5:49
    give you no reason to believe
  • 5:49 - 5:51
    that Monty won't be at the party.
  • 5:52 - 5:54
    Okay, our last topic is to distinguish
  • 5:54 - 5:56
    two different types of arguments.
  • 5:56 - 5:58
    So I'm gonna put up here, on the left,
  • 5:58 - 5:59
    the orange argument, which is the
  • 5:59 - 6:01
    second response that your friend gave,
  • 6:01 - 6:03
    "Monty's really shy" and
    "He rarely goes to parties."
  • 6:03 - 6:05
    On the right we'll put
    the purple argument,
  • 6:05 - 6:06
    "Monty's in Beijing" and
  • 6:06 - 6:08
    "He can't get from Beijing
    to the party in time."
  • 6:08 - 6:10
    Both of them have the same conclusion,
  • 6:10 - 6:12
    "Monty won't be at the party."
  • 6:12 - 6:13
    Now, as I said before, both of these
  • 6:13 - 6:15
    are good arguments, they both do
  • 6:15 - 6:16
    give you reason to believe the conclusion,
  • 6:16 - 6:18
    i.e., both of them have premises
  • 6:18 - 6:19
    which support the conclusion,
  • 6:19 - 6:21
    but there's an important difference
  • 6:21 - 6:23
    between the two arguments
    that I want to point out.
  • 6:23 - 6:25
    If you consider the purple argument,
  • 6:25 - 6:27
    and think about what those premises say,
  • 6:27 - 6:30
    you'll notice that if
    those premises are true,
  • 6:30 - 6:32
    if Monty's in Beijing,
    and can't get from Beijing
  • 6:32 - 6:35
    to the party in time, then it must be true
  • 6:35 - 6:37
    that Monty won't be at the party.
  • 6:37 - 6:41
    Those premises guarantee the conclusion.
  • 6:41 - 6:43
    In such an argument, where the premises
  • 6:43 - 6:44
    guarantee the truth of the conclusion,
  • 6:44 - 6:47
    we call the argument deductive.
  • 6:47 - 6:49
    In a deductive argument,
    given the premises,
  • 6:49 - 6:52
    the conclusion must be true.
  • 6:52 - 6:53
    Just thinking about the information
  • 6:53 - 6:55
    in the premises in a deductive argument
  • 6:55 - 6:58
    gives you all you need
    to deduce the conclusion.
  • 7:00 - 7:01
    If you look at the
    orange argument, though,
  • 7:01 - 7:03
    you'll notice that that's not the case.
  • 7:03 - 7:05
    In the orange argument,
    even if those premises
  • 7:05 - 7:09
    are true, the conclusion
    might still be false.
  • 7:09 - 7:10
    Even given that Monty is really shy
  • 7:10 - 7:13
    and rarely goes to parties,
    it's still possible
  • 7:13 - 7:15
    that he'll get over
    his shyness and suspend
  • 7:15 - 7:17
    his policy of rarely going to parties,
  • 7:17 - 7:18
    and unexpectedly show up.
  • 7:18 - 7:20
    It's unlikely, but it's possible.
  • 7:20 - 7:23
    So the truth of the premises
    in the orange argument
  • 7:23 - 7:26
    does not guarantee the
    truth of the conclusion.
  • 7:26 - 7:28
    Arguments like this, we call ampliative.
  • 7:28 - 7:32
    In an ampliative argument,
    the truth of the premises
  • 7:32 - 7:35
    makes the conclusion probable
    but doesn't guarantee it.
  • 7:35 - 7:37
    Now, as I said, both of
    the arguments are good.
  • 7:37 - 7:39
    Ampliative arguments can often be
  • 7:39 - 7:42
    very good arguments,
    they're just not deductive.
  • 7:42 - 7:45
    The premises don't guarantee
    the truth of the conclusion.
  • 7:45 - 7:46
    Now, when you're evaluating an argument,
  • 7:46 - 7:48
    it can be important to know whether or not
  • 7:48 - 7:50
    the argument is supposed to be deductive
  • 7:50 - 7:53
    or supposed to be merely ampliative.
  • 7:53 - 7:55
    If an argument is
    supposed to be deductive,
  • 7:55 - 7:57
    but careful consideration of the argument
  • 7:57 - 7:59
    reveals that in fact the premises
  • 7:59 - 8:01
    don't guarantee the
    truth of the conclusion,
  • 8:01 - 8:03
    if the conclusion could
    be false even though
  • 8:03 - 8:05
    the premises are true,
    that's often a good reason
  • 8:05 - 8:08
    to reject the argument as a bad argument.
  • 8:08 - 8:10
    Whereas in an ampliative argument,
  • 8:10 - 8:12
    to notice that the truth of the premises
  • 8:12 - 8:14
    doesn't guarantee the
    truth of the conclusion,
  • 8:14 - 8:17
    is simply to notice that
    it's an ampliative argument.
  • 8:17 - 8:19
    If you were to object
    to the orange argument
  • 8:19 - 8:21
    by pointing out that,
    still, the conclusion
  • 8:21 - 8:24
    could be false, you'd
    really be missing the point.
  • 8:24 - 8:27
    In an ampliative argument,
    it's taken for granted
  • 8:27 - 8:30
    that the conclusion is not
    guaranteed by the premises.
  • 8:30 - 8:32
    Rather, what an ampliative
    argument is doing
  • 8:32 - 8:33
    is giving you reasons to think
  • 8:33 - 8:36
    that the conclusion is probable.
  • 8:36 - 8:38
    So knowing what type of
    argument an argument is
  • 8:38 - 8:41
    is essential to knowing which tools to use
  • 8:41 - 8:43
    to evaluate whether or
    not it's a good argument.
  • 8:43 - 8:44
    And we'll talk quite a bit more
  • 8:44 - 8:47
    about different tools for
    evaluating both ampliative
  • 8:47 - 8:50
    and deductive arguments in future lessons.
  • 8:51 - 8:53
    Okay, so summing up this lesson.
  • 8:53 - 8:55
    Critical thinking is making sure
  • 8:55 - 8:57
    that we have good reasons for our beliefs,
  • 8:57 - 8:59
    where we understand a good reason as one
  • 8:59 - 9:02
    that makes the belief
    probable, or likely to be true.
  • 9:02 - 9:04
    An argument is a set of statements,
  • 9:04 - 9:06
    which we call premises,
    that together comprise
  • 9:06 - 9:08
    a reason for another statement,
  • 9:08 - 9:11
    which we call the argument's conclusion.
  • 9:11 - 9:12
    And in a good argument, the premises
  • 9:12 - 9:14
    support their conclusions, that is,
  • 9:14 - 9:17
    the premises give you a
    good reason for believing
  • 9:17 - 9:19
    the conclusion, because
    they make it probable.
  • 9:21 - 9:24
    A deductive argument is
    one where the conclusion
  • 9:24 - 9:27
    is guaranteed by the premises.
    If the premises are true,
  • 9:27 - 9:29
    then the conclusion must be true.
  • 9:29 - 9:32
    An ampliative argument
    is one where the premises
  • 9:32 - 9:33
    don't guarantee the conclusion,
  • 9:33 - 9:35
    but they do make it probable.
  • 9:35 - 9:36
    So they can still provide you
  • 9:36 - 9:40
    with good reason for
    believing the conclusion.
  • 9:40 - 9:42
    Okay, so that ends this
    introductory lesson.
Title:
Critical Thinking Fundamentals: Introduction to Critical Thinking
Description:

Geoff Pynn (Northern Illinois University) gets you started on the critical thinking journey. He tells you what critical thinking is, what an argument is, and what the difference between a deductive and an ampliative argument is.

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Team:
PACE
Duration:
09:52

English subtitles

Revisions Compare revisions