Justice: What's The Right Thing To Do? Episode 01 "THE MORAL SIDE OF MURDER"
-
0:04 - 0:08Funding for this program is provided by:
-
0:08 - 0:15Additional funding provided by
-
0:34 - 0:38This is a course about Justice and we begin with a story
-
0:38 - 0:40suppose you're the driver of a trolley car,
-
0:40 - 0:45and your trolley car is hurdling down the track at sixty miles an hour
-
0:45 - 0:49and at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the track
-
0:49 - 0:52you tried to stop but you can't
-
0:52 - 0:54your brakes don't work
-
0:54 - 0:57you feel desperate because you know
-
0:57 - 1:00that if you crash into these five workers
-
1:00 - 1:01they will all die
-
1:01 - 1:05let's assume you know that for sure
-
1:05 - 1:07and so you feel helpless
-
1:07 - 1:09until you notice that there is
-
1:09 - 1:11off to the right
-
1:11 - 1:13a side track
-
1:13 - 1:16at the end of that track
-
1:16 - 1:17there's one worker
-
1:17 - 1:19working on track
-
1:19 - 1:21you're steering wheel works
-
1:21 - 1:23so you can
-
1:23 - 1:26turn the trolley car if you want to
-
1:26 - 1:29onto this side track
-
1:29 - 1:30killing the one
-
1:30 - 1:33but sparing the five.
-
1:33 - 1:36Here's our first question
-
1:36 - 1:39what's the right thing to do?
-
1:39 - 1:40What would you do?
-
1:40 - 1:43Let's take a poll,
-
1:43 - 1:45how many
-
1:45 - 1:52would turn the trolley car onto the side track?
-
1:52 - 1:54How many wouldn't?
-
1:54 - 1:58How many would go straight ahead
-
1:58 - 2:04keep your hands up, those of you who'd go straight ahead.
-
2:04 - 2:08A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn
-
2:08 - 2:10let's hear first
-
2:10 - 2:14now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think
-
2:14 - 2:20it's the right thing to do. Let's begin with those in the majority, who would turn
-
2:20 - 2:22to go onto side track?
-
2:22 - 2:24Why would you do it,
-
2:24 - 2:26what would be your reason?
-
2:26 - 2:30Who's willing to volunteer a reason?
-
2:30 - 2:32Go ahead, stand up.
-
2:32 - 2:39Because it can't be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead.
-
2:40 - 2:42it wouldn't be right to kill five
-
2:42 - 2:47if you could kill one person instead
-
2:47 - 2:49that's a good reason
-
2:49 - 2:53that's a good reason
-
2:53 - 2:54who else?
-
2:54 - 2:57does everybody agree with that
-
2:57 - 3:01reason? go ahead.
-
3:01 - 3:04Well I was thinking it was the same reason it was on
-
3:04 - 3:059/11 we regard the people who flew the plane
-
3:05 - 3:08who flew the plane into the
-
3:08 - 3:10Pennsylvania field as heroes
-
3:10 - 3:12because they chose to kill the people on the plane
-
3:12 - 3:14and not kill more people
-
3:14 - 3:16in big buildings.
-
3:16 - 3:19So the principle there was the same on 9/11
-
3:19 - 3:22it's tragic circumstance,
-
3:22 - 3:25but better to kill one so that five can live
-
3:25 - 3:31is that the reason most of you have, those of you who would turn, yes?
-
3:31 - 3:33Let's hear now
-
3:33 - 3:34from
-
3:34 - 3:36those in the minority
-
3:36 - 3:41those who wouldn't turn.
-
3:41 - 3:46Well I think that same type of mentality that justifies genocide and totalitarianism
-
3:45 - 3:50in order to save one type of race you wipe out the other.
-
3:50 - 3:53so what would you do in this case? You would
-
3:53 - 3:55to avoid
-
3:55 - 3:58the horrors of genocide
-
3:58 - 4:04you would crash into the five and kill them?
-
4:04 - 4:08Presumably yes.
-
4:08 - 4:10okay who else?
-
4:10 - 4:14That's a brave answer, thank you.
-
4:14 - 4:16Let's consider another
-
4:17 - 4:20trolley car case
-
4:20 - 4:22and see
-
4:22 - 4:24whether
-
4:24 - 4:27those of you in the majority
-
4:27 - 4:31want to adhere to the principle,
-
4:31 - 4:34better that one should die so that five should live.
-
4:34 - 4:39This time you're not the driver of the trolley car, you're an onlooker
-
4:39 - 4:43standing on a bridge overlooking a trolley car track
-
4:43 - 4:46and down the track comes a trolley car
-
4:46 - 4:50at the end of the track are five workers
-
4:50 - 4:52the brakes don't work
-
4:52 - 4:56the trolley car is about to careen into the five and kill them
-
4:56 - 4:57and now
-
4:57 - 4:59you're not the driver
-
4:59 - 5:01you really feel helpless
-
5:01 - 5:03until you notice
-
5:03 - 5:07standing next to you
-
5:07 - 5:09leaning over
-
5:09 - 5:10the bridge
-
5:10 - 5:17is it very fat man.
-
5:17 - 5:20And you could
-
5:20 - 5:23give him a shove
-
5:23 - 5:25he would fall over the bridge
-
5:25 - 5:28onto the track
-
5:28 - 5:30right in the way of
-
5:30 - 5:32the trolley car
-
5:32 - 5:33he would die
-
5:33 - 5:39but he would spare the five.
-
5:39 - 5:41Now, how many would push
-
5:41 - 5:48the fat man over the bridge? Raise your hand.
-
5:48 - 5:51How many wouldn't?
-
5:51 - 5:54Most people wouldn't.
-
5:54 - 5:56Here's the obvious question,
-
5:56 - 5:57what became
-
5:57 - 6:00of the principle
-
6:00 - 6:05better to save five lives even if it means sacrificing one, what became of the principal
-
6:05 - 6:07that almost everyone endorsed
-
6:07 - 6:09in the first case
-
6:09 - 6:13I need to hear from someone who was in the majority in both
-
6:13 - 6:14cases is
-
6:14 - 6:18how do you explain the difference between the two?
-
6:18 - 6:22The second one I guess involves an active choice of
-
6:22 - 6:23pushing a person
-
6:23 - 6:24and down which
-
6:24 - 6:25I guess that
-
6:25 - 6:30that person himself would otherwise not have been involved in the situation at all
-
6:30 - 6:31and so
-
6:31 - 6:34to choose on his behalf I guess
-
6:34 - 6:37to
-
6:37 - 6:40involve him in something that he otherwise would have this escaped is
-
6:40 - 6:42I guess more than
-
6:42 - 6:44what you have in the first case where
-
6:44 - 6:46the three parties, the driver and
-
6:46 - 6:48the two sets of workers are
-
6:48 - 6:51already I guess in this situation.
-
6:51 - 6:55but the guy working, the one on the track off to the side
-
6:55 - 7:02he didn't choose to sacrifice his life any more than the fat guy did, did he?
-
7:02 - 7:05That's true, but he was on the tracks.
-
7:05 - 7:10this guy was on the bridge.
-
7:10 - 7:14Go ahead, you can come back if you want.
-
7:14 - 7:15Alright, it's a hard question
-
7:15 - 7:19but you did well you did very well it's a hard question.
-
7:20 - 7:21who else
-
7:21 - 7:23can
-
7:23 - 7:26find a way of reconciling
-
7:26 - 7:30the reaction of the majority in these two cases? Yes?
-
7:30 - 7:32Well I guess
-
7:32 - 7:33in the first case where
-
7:33 - 7:35you have the one worker and the five
-
7:35 - 7:37it's a choice between those two, and you have to
-
7:37 - 7:41make a certain choice and people are going to die because of the trolley car
-
7:41 - 7:45not necessarily because of your direct actions. The trolley car is a runway,
-
7:45 - 7:48thing and you need to make in a split second choice
-
7:48 - 7:53whereas pushing the fat man over is an actual act of murder on your part
-
7:53 - 7:54you have control over that
-
7:54 - 7:57whereas you may not have control over the trolley car.
-
7:57 - 8:00So I think that it's a slightly different situation.
-
8:00 - 8:04Alright who has a reply? Is that, who has a reply to that? no that was good, who has a way
-
8:04 - 8:06who wants to reply?
-
8:06 - 8:09Is that a way out of this?
-
8:09 - 8:12I don't think that's a very good reason because you choose
-
8:12 - 8:17either way you have to choose who dies because you either choose to turn and kill a person
-
8:17 - 8:18which is an act of conscious
-
8:18 - 8:20thought to turn,
-
8:20 - 8:21or you choose to push the fat man
-
8:21 - 8:24over which is also an active
-
8:24 - 8:28conscious action so either way you're making a choice.
-
8:28 - 8:30Do you want to reply?
-
8:30 - 8:34Well I'm not really sure that that's the case, it just still seems kind of different, the act of actually
-
8:34 - 8:38pushing someone over onto the tracks and killing them,
-
8:38 - 8:43you are actually killing him yourself, you're pushing him with your own hands you're pushing and
-
8:43 - 8:44that's different
-
8:44 - 8:47than steering something that is going to cause death
-
8:47 - 8:49into another...you know
-
8:49 - 8:53it doesn't really sound right saying it now when I'm up here.
-
8:53 - 8:55No that's good, what's your name?
-
8:55 - 8:56Andrew.
-
8:56 - 9:00Andrew and let me ask you this question Andrew,
-
9:00 - 9:02suppose
-
9:02 - 9:04standing on the bridge
-
9:04 - 9:05next to the fat man
-
9:05 - 9:08I didn't have to push him, suppose he was standing
-
9:08 - 9:15over a trap door that I could open by turning a steering wheel like that
-
9:17 - 9:19would you turn it?
-
9:19 - 9:21For some reason that still just seems more
-
9:21 - 9:24more wrong.
-
9:24 - 9:30I mean maybe if you just accidentally like leaned into this steering wheel or something like that
-
9:30 - 9:31or but,
-
9:31 - 9:33or say that the car is
-
9:33 - 9:38hurdling towards a switch that will drop the trap
-
9:38 - 9:39then I could agree with that.
-
9:40 - 9:42Fair enough, it still seems
-
9:42 - 9:46wrong in a way that it doesn't seem wrong in the first case to turn, you say
-
9:46 - 9:50An in another way, I mean in the first situation you're involved directly with the situation
-
9:50 - 9:52in the second one you're an onlooker as well.
-
9:52 - 9:57So you have the choice of becoming involved or not by pushing the fat man.
-
9:57 - 10:00Let's forget for the moment about this case,
-
10:00 - 10:01that's good,
-
10:01 - 10:06but let's imagine a different case. This time your doctor in an emergency room
-
10:06 - 10:12and six patients come to you
-
10:12 - 10:18they've been in a terrible trolley car wreck
-
10:18 - 10:24five of them sustained moderate injuries one is severely injured you could spend all day
-
10:24 - 10:28caring for the one severely injured victim,
-
10:28 - 10:32but in that time the five would die, or you could look after the five, restore them to health, but
-
10:32 - 10:35during that time the one severely injured
-
10:35 - 10:36person would die.
-
10:36 - 10:38How many would save
-
10:38 - 10:40the five
-
10:40 - 10:41now as the doctor?
-
10:41 - 10:44How many would save the one?
-
10:44 - 10:46Very few people,
-
10:46 - 10:49just a handful of people.
-
10:49 - 10:51Same reason I assume,
-
10:51 - 10:56one life versus five.
-
10:56 - 10:57Now consider
-
10:57 - 10:59another doctor case
-
10:59 - 11:02this time you're a transplant surgeon
-
11:02 - 11:06and you have five patients each in desperate need
-
11:06 - 11:10of an organ transplant in order to survive
-
11:10 - 11:12on needs a heart one a lung,
-
11:12 - 11:14one a kidney,
-
11:14 - 11:15one a liver
-
11:15 - 11:17and the fifth
-
11:17 - 11:20a pancreas.
-
11:20 - 11:23And you have no organ donors
-
11:23 - 11:25you are about to
-
11:25 - 11:28see you them die
-
11:28 - 11:29and then
-
11:29 - 11:31it occurs to you
-
11:31 - 11:32that in the next room
-
11:32 - 11:36there's a healthy guy who came in for a checkup.
-
11:39 - 11:44and he is
-
11:44 - 11:47you like that
-
11:47 - 11:51and he's taking a nap
-
11:53 - 11:57you could go in very quietly
-
11:57 - 12:01yank out the five organs, that person would die
-
12:01 - 12:03but you can save the five.
-
12:03 - 12:10How many would do it? Anyone?
-
12:10 - 12:17How many? Put your hands up if you would do it.
-
12:18 - 12:22Anyone in the balcony?
-
12:22 - 12:24You would? Be careful don't lean over too much
-
12:26 - 12:29How many wouldn't?
-
12:29 - 12:30All right.
-
12:30 - 12:34What do you say, speak up in the balcony, you who would
-
12:34 - 12:36yank out the organs, why?
-
12:36 - 12:39I'd actually like to explore slightly alternate
-
12:39 - 12:40possibility of just taking the one
-
12:40 - 12:44of the five he needs an organ who dies first
-
12:44 - 12:50and using their four healthy organs to save the other four
-
12:50 - 12:55That's a pretty good idea.
-
12:55 - 12:58That's a great idea
-
12:58 - 13:00except for the fact
-
13:00 - 13:06that you just wrecked the philosophical point.
-
13:06 - 13:07Let's step back
-
13:07 - 13:10from these stories and these arguments
-
13:10 - 13:13to notice a couple of things
-
13:13 - 13:18about the way the arguments have began to unfold.
-
13:18 - 13:19Certain
-
13:19 - 13:20moral principles
-
13:20 - 13:23have already begun to emerge
-
13:23 - 13:26from the discussions we've had
-
13:26 - 13:28and let's consider
-
13:28 - 13:30what those moral principles
-
13:30 - 13:31look like
-
13:31 - 13:36the first moral principle that emerged from the discussion said
-
13:36 - 13:39that the right thing to do the moral thing to do
-
13:39 - 13:43depends on the consequences that will result
-
13:43 - 13:45from your action
-
13:45 - 13:47at the end of the day
-
13:47 - 13:49better that five should live
-
13:49 - 13:52even if one must die.
-
13:52 - 13:54That's an example
-
13:54 - 13:56of consequentialist
-
13:56 - 13:59moral reasoning.
-
13:59 - 14:04consequentialist moral reasoning locates morality in the consequences of an act. In the state of the
-
14:04 - 14:07world that will result
-
14:07 - 14:09from the thing you do
-
14:09 - 14:13but then we went a little further, we considered those other cases
-
14:13 - 14:15and people weren't so sure
-
14:15 - 14:17about
-
14:17 - 14:21consequentialist moral reasoning
-
14:21 - 14:22when people hesitated
-
14:22 - 14:24to push the fat man
-
14:24 - 14:26over the bridge
-
14:26 - 14:29or to yank out the organs of the innocent
-
14:29 - 14:30patient
-
14:30 - 14:32people gestured towards
-
14:32 - 14:34reasons
-
14:34 - 14:35having to do
-
14:35 - 14:37with the intrinsic
-
14:37 - 14:39quality of the act
-
14:39 - 14:41itself.
-
14:41 - 14:43Consequences be what they may.
-
14:43 - 14:45People were reluctant
-
14:45 - 14:48people thought it was just wrong
-
14:48 - 14:49categorically wrong
-
14:49 - 14:50to kill
-
14:50 - 14:51a person
-
14:51 - 14:54an innocent person
-
14:54 - 14:55even for the sake
-
14:55 - 14:56of saving
-
14:56 - 14:58five lives, at least these people thought that
-
14:58 - 15:01in the second
-
15:01 - 15:05version of each story we reconsidered
-
15:05 - 15:07so this points
-
15:07 - 15:10a second
-
15:10 - 15:11categorical
-
15:11 - 15:13way
-
15:13 - 15:15of thinking about
-
15:15 - 15:16moral reasoning
-
15:16 - 15:22categorical moral reasoning locates morality in certain absolute moral requirements in
-
15:22 - 15:24certain categorical duties and rights
-
15:24 - 15:27regardless of the consequences.
-
15:27 - 15:29We're going to explore
-
15:29 - 15:33in the days and weeks to come the contrast between
-
15:33 - 15:37consequentialist and categorical moral principles.
-
15:37 - 15:38The most influential
-
15:38 - 15:40example of
-
15:40 - 15:46consequential moral reasoning is utilitarianism, a doctrine invented by
-
15:46 - 15:51Jeremy Bentham, the eighteenth century English political philosopher.
-
15:51 - 15:54The most important
-
15:54 - 15:57philosopher of categorical moral reasoning
-
15:57 - 15:58is the
-
15:58 - 16:03eighteenth century German philosopher Emmanuel Kant.
-
16:03 - 16:04So we will look
-
16:04 - 16:07at those two different modes of moral reasoning
-
16:07 - 16:08assess them
-
16:08 - 16:11and also consider others.
-
16:11 - 16:16If you look at the syllabus, you'll notice that we read a number of great and famous books.
-
16:16 - 16:18Books by Aristotle
-
16:18 - 16:20John Locke
-
16:20 - 16:22Emanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill,
-
16:22 - 16:24and others.
-
16:24 - 16:28You'll notice too from the syllabus that we don't only read these books,
-
16:28 - 16:30we also all
-
16:30 - 16:32take up
-
16:32 - 16:37contemporary political and legal controversies that raise philosophical questions.
-
16:37 - 16:40We will debate equality and inequality,
-
16:40 - 16:41affirmative action,
-
16:41 - 16:44free speech versus hate speech,
-
16:44 - 16:47same sex marriage, military conscription,
-
16:47 - 16:51a range of practical questions, why
-
16:51 - 16:55not just to enliven these abstract and distant books
-
16:55 - 17:01but to make clear to bring out what's at stake in our everyday lives including our political
-
17:01 - 17:04lives,
-
17:04 - 17:06for philosophy.
-
17:06 - 17:08So we will read these books
-
17:08 - 17:10and we will debate these
-
17:10 - 17:15issues and we'll see how each informs and illuminates the other.
-
17:15 - 17:18This may sound appealing enough
-
17:18 - 17:19but here
-
17:19 - 17:23I have to issue a warning,
-
17:23 - 17:25and the warning is this
-
17:25 - 17:28to read these books
-
17:28 - 17:32in this way,
-
17:32 - 17:34as an exercise in self-knowledge,
-
17:34 - 17:39to read them in this way carry certain risks
-
17:39 - 17:42risks that are both personal and political,
-
17:42 - 17:48risks that every student of political philosophy have known.
-
17:48 - 17:51These risks spring from that fact
-
17:51 - 17:53that philosophy
-
17:53 - 17:54teaches us
-
17:54 - 17:56and unsettles us
-
17:56 - 18:01by confronting us with what we already know.
-
18:01 - 18:03There's an irony
-
18:03 - 18:10the difficulty of this course consists in the fact that it teaches what you already know.
-
18:10 - 18:12It works by taking
-
18:12 - 18:16what we know from familiar unquestioned settings,
-
18:16 - 18:20and making it strange.
-
18:20 - 18:22That's how those examples worked
-
18:22 - 18:23worked
-
18:23 - 18:29the hypotheticals with which we began with their mix of playfulness and sobriety.
-
18:29 - 18:34it's also how these philosophical books work. Philosophy
-
18:34 - 18:36estranges us
-
18:36 - 18:38from the familiar
-
18:38 - 18:40not by supplying new information
-
18:40 - 18:42but by inviting
-
18:42 - 18:44and provoking
-
18:44 - 18:47a new way of seeing
-
18:47 - 18:50but, and here's the risk,
-
18:50 - 18:51once
-
18:51 - 18:54the familiar turns strange,
-
18:54 - 18:58it's never quite the same again.
-
18:58 - 19:00Self-knowledge
-
19:00 - 19:03is like lost innocence,
-
19:03 - 19:05however unsettling
-
19:05 - 19:06you find it,
-
19:06 - 19:07it can never
-
19:07 - 19:10be unthought
-
19:10 - 19:13or unknown
-
19:13 - 19:17what makes this enterprise difficult
-
19:17 - 19:20but also riveting,
-
19:20 - 19:21is that
-
19:21 - 19:25moral and political philosophy is a story
-
19:25 - 19:29and you don't know where this story will lead but what you do know
-
19:29 - 19:31is that the story
-
19:31 - 19:34is about you.
-
19:34 - 19:37Those are the personal risks,
-
19:37 - 19:40now what of the political risks.
-
19:40 - 19:43one way of introducing of course like this
-
19:43 - 19:45would be to promise you
-
19:45 - 19:46that by reading these books
-
19:46 - 19:48and debating these issues
-
19:48 - 19:52you will become a better more responsible citizen.
-
19:52 - 19:56You will examine the presuppositions of public policy, you will hone your political
-
19:56 - 19:57judgment
-
19:57 - 20:03you'll become a more effective participant in public affairs
-
20:03 - 20:07but this would be a partial and misleading promise
-
20:07 - 20:11political philosophy for the most part hasn't worked that way.
-
20:11 - 20:15You have to allow for the possibility
-
20:15 - 20:19that political philosophy may make you a worse citizen
-
20:19 - 20:22rather than a better one
-
20:22 - 20:24or at least a worse citizen
-
20:24 - 20:26before it makes you
-
20:26 - 20:28a better one
-
20:28 - 20:30and that's because philosophy
-
20:30 - 20:33is a distancing
-
20:33 - 20:35even debilitating
-
20:35 - 20:37activity
-
20:37 - 20:38And you see this
-
20:38 - 20:40going back to Socrates
-
20:40 - 20:42there's a dialogue, the Gorgias
-
20:42 - 20:45in which one of Socrates’ friends
-
20:45 - 20:46Calicles
-
20:46 - 20:47tries to talk him out
-
20:47 - 20:50of philosophizing.
-
20:50 - 20:54calicles tells Socrates philosophy is a pretty toy
-
20:54 - 20:58if one indulges in it with moderation at the right time of life
-
20:58 - 21:04but if one pursues it further than one should it is absolute ruin.
-
21:04 - 21:07Take my advice calicles says,
-
21:07 - 21:08abandon argument
-
21:08 - 21:12learn the accomplishments of active life, take
-
21:12 - 21:17for your models not those people who spend their time on these petty quibbles,
-
21:17 - 21:20but those who have a good livelihood and reputation
-
21:20 - 21:22and many other blessings.
-
21:22 - 21:27So Calicles is really saying to Socrates
-
21:27 - 21:29quit philosophizing,
-
21:29 - 21:31get real
-
21:31 - 21:35go to business school
-
21:35 - 21:38and calicles did have a point
-
21:38 - 21:40he had a point
-
21:40 - 21:42because philosophy distances us
-
21:42 - 21:45from conventions from established assumptions
-
21:45 - 21:47and from settled beliefs.
-
21:47 - 21:49those are the risks,
-
21:49 - 21:50personal and political
-
21:50 - 21:54and in the face of these risks there is a characteristic evasion,
-
21:54 - 21:57the name of the evasion is skepticism. It's the idea
-
21:57 - 21:59well it goes something like this
-
21:59 - 22:04we didn't resolve, once and for all,
-
22:04 - 22:10either the cases or the principles we were arguing when we began
-
22:10 - 22:11and if Aristotle
-
22:11 - 22:17and Locke and Kant and Mill haven't solved these questions after all of these years
-
22:17 - 22:20who are we to think
-
22:20 - 22:24that we here in Sanders Theatre over the course a semester
-
22:24 - 22:26can resolve them
-
22:26 - 22:29and so maybe it's just a matter of
-
22:29 - 22:34each person having his or her own principles and there's nothing more to be said about
-
22:34 - 22:34it
-
22:34 - 22:37no way of reasoning
-
22:37 - 22:38that's the
-
22:38 - 22:39evasion. The evasion of skepticism
-
22:39 - 22:41to which I would offer the following
-
22:41 - 22:43reply:
-
22:43 - 22:44it's true
-
22:44 - 22:48these questions have been debated for a very long time
-
22:48 - 22:49but the very fact
-
22:49 - 22:53that they have reoccurred and persisted
-
22:53 - 22:55may suggest
-
22:55 - 22:57that though they're impossible in one sense
-
22:57 - 23:00their unavoidable in another
-
23:00 - 23:02and the reason they're unavoidable
-
23:02 - 23:06the reason they're inescapable is that we live some answer
-
23:06 - 23:10to these questions every day.
-
23:10 - 23:16So skepticism, just throwing up their hands and giving up on moral reflection,
-
23:16 - 23:18is no solution
-
23:18 - 23:20Emanuel Kant
-
23:20 - 23:24described very well the problem with skepticism when he wrote
-
23:24 - 23:26skepticism is a resting place for human reason
-
23:26 - 23:29where it can reflect upon its dogmatic wanderings
-
23:29 - 23:33but it is no dwelling place for permanent settlement.
-
23:33 - 23:36Simply to acquiesce in skepticism, Kant wrote,
-
23:36 - 23:43can never suffice to overcome the restless of reason.
-
23:43 - 23:47I've tried to suggest through theses stories and these arguments
-
23:47 - 23:50some sense of the risks and temptations
-
23:50 - 23:56of the perils and the possibilities I would simply conclude by saying
-
23:56 - 23:58that the aim of this course
-
23:58 - 24:00is to awaken
-
24:00 - 24:02the restlessness of reason
-
24:02 - 24:04and to see where it might lead
-
24:04 - 24:11thank you very much.
-
24:15 - 24:17Like, in a situation that desperate,
-
24:17 - 24:21you have to do what you have to do to survive. You have to do what you have to do you? You've gotta do
-
24:21 - 24:23What you
-
24:23 - 24:24gotta do. pretty much,
-
24:24 - 24:26If you've been going nineteen days without any food
-
24:26 - 24:33someone has to take the sacrifice, someone has to make the sacrifice and people can survive. Alright that's good, what's your name? Marcus.
-
24:34 - 24:40Marcus, what do you say to Marcus?
-
24:40 - 24:45Last time
-
24:45 - 24:47we started out last time
-
24:47 - 24:49with some stores
-
24:49 - 24:51with some moral dilemmas
-
24:51 - 24:53about trolley cars
-
24:53 - 24:55and about doctors
-
24:55 - 24:56and healthy patients
-
24:56 - 24:58vulnerable
-
24:58 - 25:01to being victims of organ transplantation
-
25:01 - 25:04we noticed two things
-
25:04 - 25:07about the arguments we had
-
25:07 - 25:11one had to do with the way we were arguing
-
25:11 - 25:14it began with our judgments in particular cases
-
25:14 - 25:18we tried to articulate the reasons or the principles
-
25:18 - 25:23lying behind our judgments
-
25:23 - 25:25and then confronted with a new case
-
25:25 - 25:31we found ourselves re-examining those principles
-
25:31 - 25:34revising each in the light of the other
-
25:34 - 25:39and we noticed the built-in pressure to try to bring into alignment
-
25:39 - 25:42our judgments about particular cases
-
25:42 - 25:44and the principles we would endorse
-
25:44 - 25:46on reflection
-
25:46 - 25:51we also noticed something about the substance of the arguments
-
25:51 - 25:55that emerged from the discussion.
-
25:55 - 26:01We noticed that sometimes we were tempted to locate the morality of an act in the consequences
-
26:01 - 26:07in the results, in the state of the world that it brought about.
-
26:07 - 26:09We called is consequentialist
-
26:09 - 26:12moral reason.
-
26:12 - 26:13But we also noticed that
-
26:13 - 26:16in some cases
-
26:16 - 26:19we weren't swayed only
-
26:19 - 26:22by the results
-
26:22 - 26:23sometimes,
-
26:23 - 26:25many of us felt,
-
26:25 - 26:32that not just consequences but also the intrinsic quality or character of the act
-
26:32 - 26:35matters morally.
-
26:35 - 26:41Some people argued that there are certain things that are just categorically wrong
-
26:41 - 26:43even if they bring about
-
26:43 - 26:44a good result
-
26:44 - 26:45even
-
26:45 - 26:47if they save five people
-
26:47 - 26:50at the cost of one life.
-
26:50 - 26:53So we contrasted consequentialist
-
26:53 - 26:55moral principles
-
26:55 - 26:58with categorical ones.
-
26:58 - 27:00Today
-
27:00 - 27:01and in the next few days
-
27:01 - 27:07we will begin to examine one of the most influential
-
27:07 - 27:09versions of consequentialist
-
27:09 - 27:11moral theory
-
27:11 - 27:16and that's the philosophy of utilitarianism.
-
27:16 - 27:17Jeremy Bentham,
-
27:17 - 27:19the eighteenth century
-
27:19 - 27:22English political philosopher
-
27:22 - 27:23gave first
-
27:23 - 27:27the first clear systematic expression
-
27:27 - 27:29to the utilitarian
-
27:29 - 27:32moral theory.
-
27:32 - 27:36And Bentham's idea,
-
27:36 - 27:38his essential idea
-
27:38 - 27:43is a very simple one
-
27:43 - 27:45with a lot of
-
27:45 - 27:46morally
-
27:46 - 27:48intuitive appeal.
-
27:48 - 27:50Bentham's idea is
-
27:50 - 27:52the following
-
27:52 - 27:54the right thing to do
-
27:54 - 27:58the just thing to do
-
27:58 - 27:59it's to
-
27:59 - 28:01maximize
-
28:01 - 28:02utility.
-
28:02 - 28:06What did he mean by utility?
-
28:06 - 28:11He meant by utility the balance
-
28:11 - 28:14of pleasure over pain,
-
28:14 - 28:17happiness over suffering.
-
28:17 - 28:18Here's how we arrived
-
28:18 - 28:19at the principle
-
28:19 - 28:22of maximizing utility.
-
28:22 - 28:24He started out by observing
-
28:24 - 28:26that all of us
-
28:26 - 28:28all human beings
-
28:28 - 28:31are governed by two sovereign masters,
-
28:31 - 28:35pain and pleasure.
-
28:35 - 28:37We human beings
-
28:37 - 28:42like pleasure and dislike pain
-
28:42 - 28:46and so we should base morality
-
28:46 - 28:49whether we are thinking of what to do in our own lives
-
28:49 - 28:50or whether
-
28:50 - 28:53as legislators or citizens
-
28:53 - 28:57we are thinking about what the law should be,
-
28:57 - 29:02the right thing to do individually or collectively
-
29:02 - 29:06is to maximize, act in a way that maximizes
-
29:06 - 29:08the overall level
-
29:08 - 29:12of happiness.
-
29:12 - 29:15Bentham's utilitarianism is sometimes summed up with the slogan
-
29:15 - 29:19the greatest good for the greatest number.
-
29:19 - 29:20With this
-
29:20 - 29:23basic principle of utility on hand,
-
29:23 - 29:26let's begin to test it and to examine it
-
29:26 - 29:28by turning to another case
-
29:28 - 29:31another story but this time
-
29:31 - 29:33not a hypothetical story,
-
29:33 - 29:34a real-life story
-
29:34 - 29:35the case of
-
29:35 - 29:38the Queen versus Dudley and Stephens.
-
29:38 - 29:42This was a nineteenth-century British law case
-
29:42 - 29:44that's famous
-
29:44 - 29:48and much debated in law schools.
-
29:48 - 29:50Here's what happened in the case
-
29:50 - 29:52I'll summarize the story
-
29:52 - 29:55and then I want to hear
-
29:55 - 29:58how you would rule
-
29:58 - 30:04imagining that you are the jury.
-
30:04 - 30:06A newspaper account of the time
-
30:06 - 30:09described the background:
-
30:09 - 30:11A sadder story of disaster at sea
-
30:11 - 30:13was never told
-
30:13 - 30:15than that of the survivors of the yacht
-
30:15 - 30:16Mignonette.
-
30:16 - 30:19The ship foundered in the south Atlantic
-
30:19 - 30:22thirteen hundred miles from the cape
-
30:22 - 30:24there were four in the crew,
-
30:24 - 30:26Dudley was the captain
-
30:26 - 30:28Stephens was the first mate
-
30:28 - 30:30Brooks was a sailor,
-
30:30 - 30:31all men of
-
30:31 - 30:32excellent character,
-
30:32 - 30:34or so the newspaper account
-
30:34 - 30:36tells us.
-
30:36 - 30:39The fourth crew member was the cabin boy,
-
30:39 - 30:40Richard Parker
-
30:40 - 30:43seventeen years old.
-
30:43 - 30:45He was an orphan
-
30:45 - 30:47he had no family
-
30:47 - 30:51and he was on his first long voyage at sea.
-
30:51 - 30:54He went, the news account tells us,
-
30:54 - 30:57rather against the advice of his friends.
-
30:57 - 31:00He went in the hopefulness of youthful ambition
-
31:00 - 31:03thinking the journey would make a man of him.
-
31:03 - 31:05Sadly it was not to be,
-
31:05 - 31:08the facts of the case were not in dispute,
-
31:08 - 31:09a wave hit the ship
-
31:09 - 31:12and the Mignonette went down.
-
31:12 - 31:15The four crew members escaped to a lifeboat
-
31:15 - 31:16the only
-
31:16 - 31:18food they had
-
31:18 - 31:20were two
-
31:20 - 31:21cans of preserved
-
31:21 - 31:22turnips
-
31:22 - 31:24no fresh water
-
31:24 - 31:27for the first three days they ate nothing
-
31:27 - 31:30on the fourth day that opened one of the cans of turnips
-
31:30 - 31:32and ate it.
-
31:32 - 31:34The next day they caught a turtle
-
31:34 - 31:37together with the other can of turnips
-
31:37 - 31:39the turtle
-
31:39 - 31:40enabled them to subsist
-
31:40 - 31:43for the next few days and then for eight days
-
31:43 - 31:44they had nothing
-
31:44 - 31:47no food no water.
-
31:47 - 31:50Imagine yourself in a situation like that
-
31:50 - 31:53what would you do?
-
31:53 - 31:55Here's what they did
-
31:55 - 32:01by now the cabin boy Parker is lying at the bottom of the lifeboat in a corner
-
32:01 - 32:03because he had drunk sea water
-
32:03 - 32:05against the advice of the others
-
32:05 - 32:07and he had become ill
-
32:07 - 32:11and he appeared to be dying
-
32:11 - 32:15so on the nineteenth day Dudley, the captain, suggested
-
32:15 - 32:17that they should all
-
32:17 - 32:19have a lottery. That they should
-
32:19 - 32:20all draw lots to see
-
32:20 - 32:21who would die
-
32:21 - 32:24to save the rest.
-
32:24 - 32:25Brooks
-
32:25 - 32:27refused
-
32:27 - 32:29he didn't like the lottery idea
-
32:29 - 32:31we don't know whether this
-
32:31 - 32:36was because he didn't want to take that chance or because he believed in categorical moral
-
32:36 - 32:37principles
-
32:37 - 32:39but in any case
-
32:39 - 32:42no lots were drawn.
-
32:42 - 32:43The next day
-
32:43 - 32:45there was still no ship in sight
-
32:45 - 32:48so a Dudley told Brooks to avert his gaze
-
32:48 - 32:51and he motioned to Stephens
-
32:51 - 32:54that the boy Parker had better be killed.
-
32:54 - 32:56Dudley offered a prayer
-
32:56 - 32:58he told a the boy his time had come
-
32:58 - 33:01and he killed him with a pen knife
-
33:01 - 33:04stabbing him in the jugular vein.
-
33:04 - 33:10Brooks emerged from his conscientious objection to share in the gruesome bounty.
-
33:10 - 33:11For four days
-
33:11 - 33:15the three of them fed on the body and blood of the cabin boy.
-
33:15 - 33:17True story.
-
33:17 - 33:19And then they were rescued.
-
33:19 - 33:23Dudley describes their rescue
-
33:23 - 33:25in his diary
-
33:25 - 33:28with staggering euphemism, quote:
-
33:28 - 33:30"on the twenty fourth day
-
33:30 - 33:35as we were having our breakfast
-
33:35 - 33:39a ship appeared at last."
-
33:39 - 33:44The three survivors were picked up by a German ship. They were taken back to Falmouth in England
-
33:44 - 33:47where they were arrested and tried
-
33:47 - 33:48Brooks
-
33:48 - 33:50turned state's witness
-
33:50 - 33:54Dudley and Stephens went to trial. They didn't dispute the facts
-
33:54 - 33:55they claimed
-
33:55 - 33:58they had acted out of necessity
-
33:58 - 33:59that was their defense
-
33:59 - 34:01they argued in effect
-
34:01 - 34:03better that one should die
-
34:03 - 34:06so that three could survive
-
34:06 - 34:09the prosecutor
-
34:09 - 34:11wasn't swayed by that argument
-
34:11 - 34:13he said murder is murder
-
34:13 - 34:16and so the case went to trial. Now imagine you are the jury
-
34:16 - 34:19and just to simplify the discussion
-
34:19 - 34:22put aside the question of law,
-
34:22 - 34:23and let's assume that
-
34:23 - 34:26you as the jury
-
34:26 - 34:28are charged with deciding
-
34:28 - 34:31whether what they did was morally
-
34:31 - 34:34permissible or not.
-
34:34 - 34:37How many
-
34:37 - 34:40would vote
-
34:40 - 34:47not guilty, that what they did was morally permissible?
-
34:50 - 34:52And how many would vote guilty
-
34:52 - 34:55what they did was morally wrong?
-
34:55 - 34:58A pretty sizable majority.
-
34:58 - 35:04Now let's see what people's reasons are, and let me begin with those who are in the minority.
-
35:04 - 35:08Let's hear first from the defense
-
35:08 - 35:10of Dudley and Stephens.
-
35:10 - 35:14Why would you morally exonerate them?
-
35:14 - 35:18What are your reasons?
-
35:18 - 35:21I think it's I think it is morally reprehensible
-
35:21 - 35:24but I think that there's a distinction between what's morally reprehensible
-
35:24 - 35:27what makes someone legally accountable
-
35:27 - 35:31in other words the night as the judge said what's always moral isn't necessarily
-
35:31 - 35:35against the law and while I don't think that necessity
-
35:35 - 35:36justifies
-
35:36 - 35:39theft or murder any illegal act,
-
35:39 - 35:44at some point your degree of necessity does in fact
-
35:44 - 35:46exonerate you form any guilt. ok.
-
35:46 - 35:51other defenders, other voices for the defense?
-
35:51 - 35:53Moral justifications for
-
35:53 - 35:57what they did?
-
35:57 - 35:58yes, thank you
-
35:58 - 35:59
-
35:59 - 36:00I just feel like
-
36:00 - 36:03in a situation that desperate you have to do what you have to do to survive.
-
36:03 - 36:05You have to do what you have to do
-
36:05 - 36:07ya, you gotta do what you gotta do, pretty much.
-
36:07 - 36:08If you've been
-
36:08 - 36:10going nineteen days without any food
-
36:10 - 36:15you know someone just has to take the sacrifice has to make sacrifices and people can survive
-
36:15 - 36:16and furthermore from that
-
36:16 - 36:21let's say they survived and then they become productive members of society who go home and then start like
-
36:21 - 36:26a million charity organizations and this and that and this and that, I mean they benefit everybody in the end so
-
36:26 - 36:29I mean I don't know what they did afterwards, I mean they might have
-
36:29 - 36:30gone on and killed more people
-
36:30 - 36:33but whatever.
-
36:33 - 36:36what? what if they were going home and turned out to be assassins?
-
36:36 - 36:39What if they were going home and turned out to be assassins?
-
36:39 - 36:43You would want to know who they assassinated.
-
36:43 - 36:46That's true too, that's fair
-
36:46 - 36:50I would wanna know who they assassinated.
-
36:50 - 36:51alright that's good, what's your name? Marcus.
-
36:51 - 36:52We've heard a defense
-
36:52 - 36:54a couple voices for the defense
-
36:54 - 36:56now we need to hear
-
36:56 - 36:57from the prosecution
-
36:57 - 36:59most people think
-
36:59 - 37:05what they did was wrong, why?
-
37:05 - 37:10One of the first things that I was thinking was, oh well if they haven't been eating for a really long time,
-
37:10 - 37:11maybe
-
37:11 - 37:12then
-
37:12 - 37:15they're mentally affected
-
37:15 - 37:16that could be used for the defense,
-
37:16 - 37:21a possible argument that oh,
-
37:21 - 37:24that they weren't in a proper state of mind, they were making
-
37:24 - 37:29decisions that they otherwise wouldn't be making, and if that's an appealing argument
-
37:29 - 37:34that you have to be in an altered mindset to do something like that it suggests that
-
37:34 - 37:36people who find that argument convincing
-
37:36 - 37:40do you think that they're acting immorally. But I want to know what you think you're defending
-
37:40 - 37:41you k 0:37:41.249,0:37:45.549 you voted to convict right? yeah I don't think that they acted in morally
-
37:46 - 37:49appropriate way. And why not? What do you say, Here's Marcus
-
37:49 - 37:51he just defended them,
-
37:51 - 37:53he said,
-
37:53 - 37:54you heard what he said,
-
37:54 - 37:55yes I did
-
37:55 - 37:57yes
-
37:57 - 38:00that you've got to do what you've got to do in a case like that.
-
38:00 - 38:05What do you say to Marcus?
-
38:05 - 38:06They didn't,
-
38:06 - 38:13that there is no situation that would allow human beings to take
-
38:14 - 38:18the idea of fate or the other people's lives into their own hands that we don't have
-
38:18 - 38:19that kind of power.
-
38:19 - 38:21Good, okay
-
38:21 - 38:24thanks you, and what's your name?
-
38:24 - 38:25Britt? okay.
-
38:25 - 38:26who else?
-
38:26 - 38:28What do you say? Stand up
-
38:28 - 38:35I'm wondering if Dudley and Stephens had asked for Richard Parker's consent in, you know, dying,
-
38:35 - 38:38if that would
-
38:38 - 38:41would that exonerate them
-
38:41 - 38:45from an act of murder, and if so is that still morally justifiable?
-
38:45 - 38:52That's interesting, alright consent, now hang on, what's your name? Kathleen.
-
38:52 - 38:56Kathleen says suppose so what would that scenario look like?
-
38:56 - 38:57so in the story
-
38:57 - 39:00Dudley is there, pen knife in hand,
-
39:00 - 39:03but instead of the prayer
-
39:03 - 39:05or before the prayer,
-
39:05 - 39:08he says, Parker,
-
39:08 - 39:12would you mind
-
39:12 - 39:14we're desperately hungry,
-
39:14 - 39:18as Marcus empathizes with
-
39:18 - 39:20we're desperately hungry
-
39:20 - 39:22you're not going to last long anyhow,
-
39:22 - 39:23you can be a martyr,
-
39:23 - 39:26would you be a martyr
-
39:26 - 39:29how about it Parker?
-
39:29 - 39:33Then, then
-
39:33 - 39:38then what do you think, would be morally justified then? Suppose
-
39:38 - 39:38Parker
-
39:38 - 39:40in his semi-stupor
-
39:40 - 39:42says okay
-
39:42 - 39:48I don't think it'll be morally justifiable but I'm wondering. Even then, even then it wouldn't be? No
-
39:48 - 39:51You don't think that even with consent
-
39:51 - 39:52it would be morally justified.
-
39:52 - 39:55Are there people who think
-
39:55 - 39:56who want to take up Kathleen's
-
39:56 - 39:57consent idea
-
39:57 - 40:02and who think that that would make it morally justified? Raise your hand if it would
-
40:02 - 40:06if you think it would.
-
40:06 - 40:08That's very interesting
-
40:08 - 40:09Why would consent
-
40:09 - 40:16make a moral difference? Why would it?
-
40:16 - 40:19Well I just think that if he was making his own original idea
-
40:19 - 40:21and it was his idea to start with
-
40:21 - 40:24then that would be the only situation in which I would
-
40:24 - 40:26see it being appropriate in anyway 0:40:25.940,0:40:28.359 because that way you couldn't make the argument that
-
40:28 - 40:31he was pressured you know it’s three
-
40:31 - 40:33to one or whatever the ratio was,
-
40:33 - 40:34and I think that
-
40:34 - 40:38if he was making a decision to give his life then he took on the agency
-
40:38 - 40:43to sacrifice himself which some people might see as admirable and other people
-
40:43 - 40:45might disagree with that decision.
-
40:45 - 40:49So if he came up with the idea
-
40:49 - 40:53that's the only kind of consent we could have confidence in
-
40:53 - 40:55morally, then it would be okay
-
40:55 - 40:57otherwise
-
40:57 - 41:00it would be kind of coerced consent
-
41:00 - 41:01under the circumstances
-
41:01 - 41:05you think.
-
41:05 - 41:07Is there anyone who thinks
-
41:07 - 41:11that the even the consent of Parker
-
41:11 - 41:13would not justify
-
41:13 - 41:15their killing him?
-
41:15 - 41:18Who thinks that?
-
41:18 - 41:20Yes, tell us why, stand up
-
41:20 - 41:21I think that Parker
-
41:21 - 41:22would be killed
-
41:22 - 41:27with the hope that the other crew members would be rescued so
-
41:27 - 41:29there's no definite reason that he should be killed
-
41:29 - 41:31because you don't know
-
41:31 - 41:36when they're going to get rescued so if you kill him you're killing him in vain
-
41:36 - 41:38do you keep killing a crew member until you're rescued and then you're left with no one?
-
41:38 - 41:40because someone's going to die eventually?
-
41:40 - 41:44Well the moral logic of the situation seems to be that.
-
41:44 - 41:46That they would
-
41:46 - 41:50keep on picking off the weakest maybe, one by one,
-
41:50 - 41:52until they were
-
41:52 - 41:58rescued and in this case luckily when three at least were still alive.
-
41:58 - 41:59Now if
-
41:59 - 42:01if Parker did give his consent
-
42:01 - 42:04would it be all right do you think or not?
-
42:04 - 42:06No, it still wouldn't be right.
-
42:06 - 42:08Tell us why wouldn't be all right.
-
42:08 - 42:10First of all, cannibalism, I believe
-
42:10 - 42:13is morally incorrect
-
42:13 - 42:15so you shouldn’t be eating a human anyway.
-
42:15 - 42:17So
-
42:17 - 42:19cannibalism is morally objectionable outside
-
42:19 - 42:22so then even in the scenario
-
42:22 - 42:25of waiting until someone died
-
42:25 - 42:27still it would be objectionable.
-
42:27 - 42:28Yes, to me personally
-
42:28 - 42:30I feel like of
-
42:30 - 42:31it all depends on
-
42:31 - 42:35one's personal morals, like we can't just, like this is just my opinion
-
42:35 - 42:39of course other people are going to disagree.
-
42:39 - 42:41Well let's see, let's hear what their disagreements are
-
42:41 - 42:43and then we'll see
-
42:43 - 42:44if they have reasons
-
42:44 - 42:46that can persuade you or not.
-
42:46 - 42:48Let's try that
-
42:48 - 42:50Let's
-
42:50 - 42:53now is there someone
-
42:53 - 42:58who can explain, those of you who are tempted by consent
-
42:58 - 43:00can you explain
-
43:00 - 43:02why consent makes
-
43:02 - 43:03such a moral difference,
-
43:03 - 43:06what about the lottery idea
-
43:06 - 43:09does that count as consent. Remember at the beginning
-
43:09 - 43:11Dudley proposed a lottery
-
43:11 - 43:14suppose that they had agreed
-
43:14 - 43:16to a lottery
-
43:16 - 43:17then
-
43:17 - 43:21how many would then say
-
43:21 - 43:24it was all right. Say there was a lottery,
-
43:24 - 43:25cabin boy lost,
-
43:25 - 43:32and the rest of the story unfolded. How many people would say it's morally permissible?
-
43:33 - 43:37So the numbers are rising if we add a lottery, let's hear from one of you
-
43:37 - 43:42for whom the lottery would make a moral difference
-
43:42 - 43:43why would it?
-
43:43 - 43:45I think the essential
-
43:45 - 43:46element,
-
43:46 - 43:48in my mind that makes it a crime is
-
43:48 - 43:54the idea that they decided at some point that their lives were more important than his, and that
-
43:54 - 43:57I mean that's kind of the basis for really any crime
-
43:57 - 43:58right? It's like
-
43:58 - 44:02my needs, my desire is a more important than yours and mine take precedent
-
44:02 - 44:05and if they had done a lottery were everyone consented
-
44:05 - 44:06that someone should die
-
44:06 - 44:09and it's sort of like they're all sacrificing themselves,
-
44:09 - 44:11to save the rest,
-
44:11 - 44:13Then it would be all right?
-
44:13 - 44:16A little grotesque but,
-
44:16 - 44:19But morally permissible? Yes.
-
44:19 - 44:23what's your name? Matt.
-
44:23 - 44:26so, Matt for you
-
44:26 - 44:27what bothers you is not
-
44:27 - 44:31the cannibalism, but the lack of due process.
-
44:31 - 44:35I guess you could say that
-
44:35 - 44:38And can someone who agrees with Matt
-
44:38 - 44:40say a little bit more
-
44:40 - 44:41about why
-
44:41 - 44:44a lottery
-
44:44 - 44:47would make it, in your view,
-
44:47 - 44:51morally permissible.
-
44:51 - 44:56The way I understood it originally was that that was the whole issue is that the cabin boy was never
-
44:56 - 44:56consulted
-
44:56 - 45:00about whether or not it something was going to happen to him even though with the original
-
45:00 - 45:01lottery
-
45:01 - 45:04whether or not he would be a part of that it was just decided
-
45:04 - 45:08that he was the one that was going to die. Yes that's what happened in the actual case
-
45:08 - 45:12but if there were a lottery and they all agreed to the procedure
-
45:12 - 45:14you think that would be okay?
-
45:14 - 45:16Right, because everyone knows that there's gonna be a death
-
45:16 - 45:17whereas
-
45:17 - 45:19you know the cabin boy didn't know that
-
45:19 - 45:21this discussion was even happening
-
45:21 - 45:22there was no
-
45:22 - 45:24you know forewarning
-
45:24 - 45:29for him to know that hey, I may be the one that's dying. Okay, now suppose the everyone agrees
-
45:29 - 45:35to the lottery they have the lottery the cabin boy loses any changes his mind.
-
45:35 - 45:41You've already decided, it's like a verbal contract, you can't go back on that. You've decided the decision was made
-
45:41 - 45:45you know if you know you're dying for the reason for at others to live,
-
45:45 - 45:46you would, you know
-
45:46 - 45:48if the someone else had died
-
45:48 - 45:52you know that you would consume them, so
-
45:52 - 45:57But then he could say I know, but I lost.
-
45:57 - 46:02I just think that that's the whole moral issue is that there was no consulting of the cabin boy and that that's
-
46:02 - 46:04what makes it the most horrible
-
46:04 - 46:09is that he had no idea what was even going on, that if he had known what was going on
-
46:09 - 46:11it would
-
46:11 - 46:13be a bit more understandable.
-
46:13 - 46:15Alright, good, now I want to hear
-
46:15 - 46:17so there's some who think
-
46:17 - 46:19it's morally permissible
-
46:19 - 46:24but only about twenty percent,
-
46:24 - 46:27led by Marcus,
-
46:27 - 46:28then there are some who say
-
46:28 - 46:30the real problem here
-
46:30 - 46:33is the lack of consent
-
46:33 - 46:37whether the lack of consent to a lottery to a fair procedure
-
46:37 - 46:39or
-
46:39 - 46:40Kathleen's idea,
-
46:40 - 46:41lack of consent
-
46:41 - 46:43at the moment
-
46:43 - 46:45of death
-
46:45 - 46:48and if we add consent
-
46:48 - 46:49then
-
46:49 - 46:52more people are willing to consider
-
46:52 - 46:55the sacrifice morally justified.
-
46:55 - 46:57I want to hear now finally
-
46:57 - 46:59from those of you who think
-
46:59 - 47:00even with consent
-
47:00 - 47:02even with a lottery
-
47:02 - 47:03even with
-
47:03 - 47:05a final
-
47:05 - 47:07murmur of consent from Parker
-
47:07 - 47:08at the
-
47:08 - 47:09very last moment
-
47:09 - 47:11it would still
-
47:11 - 47:13be wrong
-
47:13 - 47:14and why would it be wrong
-
47:14 - 47:17that's what I want to hear.
-
47:17 - 47:19well the whole time
-
47:19 - 47:23I've been leaning towards the categorical moral reasoning
-
47:23 - 47:26and I think that
-
47:26 - 47:30there's a possibility I'd be okay with the idea of the lottery and then loser
-
47:30 - 47:31taking into their own hands to
-
47:31 - 47:33kill themselves
-
47:33 - 47:34
-
47:34 - 47:37so there wouldn't be an act of murder but I still think that
-
47:37 - 47:42even that way it's coerced and also I don't think that there's any remorse like in
-
47:42 - 47:43Dudley's diary
-
47:43 - 47:45we're getting our breakfast
-
47:45 - 47:48it seems as though he's just sort of like, oh,
-
47:48 - 47:51you know that whole idea of not valuing someone else's life
-
47:51 - 47:54so that makes me
-
47:54 - 47:58feel like I have to take the categorical stance. You want to throw the book at him.
-
47:58 - 48:02when he lacks remorse or a sense of having done anything wrong. Right.
-
48:02 - 48:07Alright, good so are there any other
-
48:07 - 48:09defenders who
-
48:09 - 48:13who say it's just categorically wrong, with or without consent, yes stand up. Why?
-
48:13 - 48:17I think undoubtedly the way our society is shaped, murder is murder
-
48:17 - 48:22murder is murder and every way our society looks down at it in the same light
-
48:22 - 48:25and I don't think it's any different in any case. Good now let me ask you a question,
-
48:25 - 48:27there were three lives at stake
-
48:27 - 48:30versus one,
-
48:30 - 48:33the one, that the cabin boy, he had no family
-
48:33 - 48:35he had no dependents,
-
48:35 - 48:39these other three had families back home in England they had dependents
-
48:39 - 48:41they had wives and children
-
48:41 - 48:43think back to Bentham,
-
48:43 - 48:45Bentham says we have to consider
-
48:45 - 48:48the welfare, the utility, the happiness
-
48:48 - 48:51of everybody. We have to add it all up
-
48:51 - 48:55so it's not just numbers three against one
-
48:55 - 48:59it's also all of those people at home
-
48:59 - 49:01in fact the London newspaper at the time
-
49:01 - 49:04and popular opinion sympathized with them
-
49:04 - 49:05Dudley in Stephens
-
49:05 - 49:08and the paper said if they weren't
-
49:08 - 49:08motivated
-
49:08 - 49:10by affection
-
49:10 - 49:13and concern for their loved ones at home and dependents, surely they wouldn't have
-
49:13 - 49:16done this. Yeah, and how is that any different from people
-
49:16 - 49:17on the corner
-
49:17 - 49:21trying to having the same desire to feed their family, I don't think it's any different. I think in any case
-
49:21 - 49:25if I'm murdering you to advance my status, that's murder and I think that we should look at all
-
49:25 - 49:28of that in the same light. Instead of criminalizing certain
-
49:28 - 49:30activities
-
49:30 - 49:34and making certain things seem more violent and savage
-
49:34 - 49:37when in that same case it's all the same act and mentality
-
49:37 - 49:40that goes into the murder, a necessity to feed their families.
-
49:40 - 49:43Suppose there weren't three, supposed there were thirty,
-
49:43 - 49:45three hundred,
-
49:45 - 49:47one life to save three hundred
-
49:47 - 49:48or in more time,
-
49:48 - 49:50three thousand
-
49:50 - 49:51or suppose the stakes were even bigger.
-
49:51 - 49:53Suppose the stakes were even bigger
-
49:53 - 49:55I think it's still the same deal.
-
49:55 - 49:58Do you think Bentham was wrong to say the right thing to do
-
49:58 - 49:59is to add
-
49:59 - 50:02up the collected happiness, you think he's wrong about that?
-
50:02 - 50:07I don't think he is wrong, but I think murder is murder in any case. Well then Bentham has to be wrong
-
50:07 - 50:10if you're right he's wrong. okay then he's wrong.
-
50:10 - 50:13Alright thank you, well done.
-
50:13 - 50:14Alright, let's step back
-
50:14 - 50:16from this discussion
-
50:16 - 50:20and notice
-
50:20 - 50:23how many objections have we heard to what they did.
-
50:23 - 50:26we heard some defenses of what they did
-
50:26 - 50:29the defense has had to do with
-
50:29 - 50:29necessity
-
50:29 - 50:33the dire circumstance and,
-
50:33 - 50:33implicitly at least,
-
50:33 - 50:36the idea that numbers matter
-
50:36 - 50:38and not only numbers matter
-
50:38 - 50:40but the wider effects matter
-
50:40 - 50:43their families back home, their dependents
-
50:43 - 50:45Parker was an orphan,
-
50:45 - 50:48no one would miss him.
-
50:48 - 50:50so if you
-
50:50 - 50:51add up
-
50:51 - 50:53if you tried to calculate
-
50:53 - 50:54the balance
-
50:54 - 50:57of happiness and suffering
-
50:57 - 50:59you might have a case for
-
50:59 - 51:03saying what they did was the right thing
-
51:03 - 51:09then we heard at least three different types of objections,
-
51:09 - 51:12we heard an objection that's said
-
51:12 - 51:14what they did was categorically wrong,
-
51:14 - 51:16right here at the end
-
51:16 - 51:17categorically wrong.
-
51:17 - 51:20Murder is murder it's always wrong
-
51:20 - 51:21even if
-
51:21 - 51:23it increases the overall happiness
-
51:23 - 51:26of society
-
51:26 - 51:28the categorical objection.
-
51:28 - 51:31But we still need to investigate
-
51:31 - 51:33why murder
-
51:33 - 51:35is categorically wrong.
-
51:35 - 51:39Is it because
-
51:39 - 51:42even cabin boys have certain fundamental rights?
-
51:42 - 51:44And if that's the reason
-
51:44 - 51:48where do those rights come from if not from some idea
-
51:48 - 51:53of the larger welfare or utility or happiness? Question number one.
-
51:53 - 51:56Others said
-
51:56 - 51:58a lottery would make a difference
-
51:58 - 52:00a fair procedure,
-
52:00 - 52:06Matt said.
-
52:06 - 52:09And some people were swayed by that.
-
52:09 - 52:12That's not a categorical objection exactly
-
52:12 - 52:14it's saying
-
52:14 - 52:17everybody has to be counted as an equal
-
52:17 - 52:18even though, at the end of the day
-
52:18 - 52:21one can be sacrificed
-
52:21 - 52:23for the general welfare.
-
52:23 - 52:26That leaves us with another question to investigate,
-
52:26 - 52:30Why does agreement to certain procedure,
-
52:30 - 52:32even a fair procedure,
-
52:32 - 52:35justify whatever result flows
-
52:35 - 52:38from the operation of that procedure?
-
52:38 - 52:40Question number two.
-
52:40 - 52:42and question number three
-
52:42 - 52:45the basic idea of consent.
-
52:45 - 52:49Kathleen got us on to this.
-
52:49 - 52:53If the cabin boy had agreed himself
-
52:53 - 52:54and not under duress
-
52:54 - 52:57as was added
-
52:57 - 53:02then it would be all right to take his life to save the rest.
-
53:02 - 53:05Even more people signed on to that idea
-
53:05 - 53:07but that raises
-
53:07 - 53:09a third philosophical question
-
53:09 - 53:11what is the moral work
-
53:11 - 53:13that consent
-
53:13 - 53:14does?
-
53:14 - 53:17Why does an act of consent
-
53:17 - 53:19make such a moral difference
-
53:19 - 53:24that an act that would be wrong, taking a life, without consent
-
53:24 - 53:25is morally
-
53:25 - 53:26permissible
-
53:26 - 53:30with consent?
-
53:30 - 53:32To investigate those three questions
-
53:32 - 53:34we're going to have to read some philosophers
-
53:34 - 53:36and starting next time
-
53:36 - 53:37we're going to read
-
53:37 - 53:38Bentham,
-
53:38 - 53:44and John Stuart Mill, utilitarian philosophers.
-
53:44 - 53:47Don't miss the chance to interact online with other viewers of Justice
-
53:44 - 53:47join the conversation,
-
53:50 - 53:57take a pop quiz, watch lectures you've missed, and a lot more. Visit www.justiceharvard.org. It's the right thing to do.
-
54:36 - 54:40Funding for the program is provided by
-
54:40 - 54:42Additional funding provided by
- Title:
- Justice: What's The Right Thing To Do? Episode 01 "THE MORAL SIDE OF MURDER"
- Description:
-
PART ONE: THE MORAL SIDE OF MURDER
If you had to choose between (1) killing one person to save the lives of five others and (2) doing nothing even though you knew that five people would die right before your eyes if you did nothing—what would you do? What would be the right thing to do? Thats the hypothetical scenario Professor Michael Sandel uses to launch his course on moral reasoning. After the majority of students votes for killing the one person in order to save the lives of five others, Sandel presents three similar moral conundrums—each one artfully designed to make the decision more difficult. As students stand up to defend their conflicting choices, it becomes clear that the assumptions behind our moral reasoning are often contradictory, and the question of what is right and what is wrong is not always black and white.PART TWO: THE CASE FOR CANNIBALISM
Sandel introduces the principles of utilitarian philosopher, Jeremy Bentham, with a famous nineteenth century legal case involving a shipwrecked crew of four. After nineteen days lost at sea, the captain decides to kill the weakest amongst them, the young cabin boy, so that the rest can feed on his blood and body to survive. The case sets up a classroom debate about the moral validity of utilitarianism—and its doctrine that the right thing to do is whatever produces "the greatest good for the greatest number."
- Video Language:
- English
- Team:
PACE
- Duration:
- 54:56