The Evolution of Human Communication and Language
-
0:02 - 0:05Thank you Clark and you all for coming along
-
0:05 - 0:07Delighted to be here...
-
0:07 - 0:11I'm really looking forward to spending this quarter at UCLA
-
0:11 - 0:15Plenty of people with overlapping research interests.
-
0:15 - 0:17As Clark says, I'm going to talk today
-
0:17 - 0:20about the evolution of human communication and languages,
-
0:20 - 0:23what I spend most my career today researching.
-
0:23 - 0:26There's the book –I might just as well hold it up!
-
0:26 - 0:29I didn't tell anybody (no, no, I'm joking) [laughs]
-
0:29 - 0:32But before I talk about language, given that I'm here for a quarter
-
0:32 - 0:37and I would like to talk to lots people and wider intellectual world while I'm here,
-
0:37 - 0:40I just wanted to briefly mention a couple other things I'm generally interested in.
-
0:40 - 0:46I've got a paper short of coming out on recursive mindreading, the idea that...
-
0:46 - 0:50this guy is thinking; she's thinking about what he's thinking;
-
0:50 - 0:54he can think about what she's thinking about what he's thinking and
-
0:54 - 0:55so on and so forth.
-
0:55 - 0:58Something that, although simple mind-reading is much studied, recursive mind-reading
-
0:58 - 1:05is not much studied, but it seems to me vital for a lot of critical human institutions, behaviors...
-
1:05 - 1:08And it's something I've become very interested in lately.
-
1:08 - 1:11And I've also become very interested in cultural attraction, which is
-
1:11 - 1:14an approach to thinking about culture and cultural evolution
-
1:14 - 1:19developed first by Dan Sperber and then by others such as
-
1:19 - 1:22Pascal Boyer and Lawrence Hirschfeld and so on.
-
1:22 - 1:27So these are just two things that I'm interested in general at the moment.
-
1:27 - 1:33I'm going to be collaborating with Jacob, who's just there, on cultural attraction while I'm here.
-
1:33 - 1:36But yes, as Clark said, today I'm going to talk about
-
1:36 - 1:41the origins and evolution of human communication and language.
-
1:42 - 1:46So the origins of human language is something with a long intellectual history.
-
1:46 - 1:49It goes back pre-Darwin...
-
1:49 - 1:53Several intellectuals have written about it...
-
1:53 - 1:57Jean-Jacques Rousseau is the most well-known of the pre-Darwinians (...)
-
1:57 - 2:04Darwin himself wrote about the origins of language for several pages in The Descent of Man.
-
2:04 - 2:07And there's been interest in it throughout the 20th century,
-
2:07 - 2:09I guess the clearest manifestation of that is the many
-
2:09 - 2:15ape-language experiments that took place from, I guess, from the 1920s onwards.
-
2:16 - 2:22And then 1960, a famous paper by a linguist called Charles Hockett...
-
2:22 - 2:26where he outlined what he called the designed features of language.
-
2:26 - 2:31Features of languages, that languages have which, in Charles Hockett's view,
-
2:31 - 2:37made languages what they are, made them languages. And he wrote about comparing them with other
-
2:37 - 2:42communication systems in the natural world. For instance, the bee dance, echolocation,
-
2:42 - 2:44and so on and so forth.
-
2:46 - 2:50And then since around the last 20, 25 years or so
-
2:50 - 2:56these various different streams of interest, from linguistics, from biology,
-
2:56 - 3:00from primatology, and so on, have come together a bit more. And there's now a healthy
-
3:00 - 3:06community of people studying language origins and evolution under the name Evolang.
-
3:06 - 3:09Conferences have been running since 1996.
-
3:11 - 3:17And the field I guess is mature enough that there's now in Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution.
-
3:17 - 3:21This is a big book, it's 800-pages long. This is published in 2011.
-
3:22 - 3:27And on its back cover it sort of says what its objectives are, and I actually agree that it
-
3:27 - 3:31does do what it says on the tin: this is a book where leading scholars
-
3:31 - 3:35present critical accounts of every aspect of the field.
-
3:35 - 3:39A wide-ranging summation of the work in all the disciplines involved.
-
3:39 - 3:43So this is proposed to be, and I agree, an accurate portrayal of where we are in
-
3:43 - 3:45the field language evolution.
-
3:47 - 3:50You look in the index and you look up the number of entries
-
3:50 - 3:54listed under different sub-disciplines of linguistics,
-
3:54 - 4:00and this is what you find... Syntax and related terms, semantics and related terms: plenty of entries;
-
4:00 - 4:05almost nothing on pragmatics. Pragmatics is kind of the messy part of language,
-
4:05 - 4:12is a bit that deals with language use in context. So if you think of semantics as meaning in isolation,
-
4:12 - 4:15pragmatics is meaning in context.
-
4:15 - 4:19So what we say is not always the same as what we mean, and
-
4:19 - 4:24pragmatics deals with that difference. It's stuff that's used in metaphor and
-
4:24 - 4:28irony and various ambiguity, and various other topics.
-
4:28 - 4:31But yet we're barely thinking about it in language evolution.
-
4:34 - 4:40Instead what we're doing is thinking of languages as... more like digital codes,
-
4:42 - 4:46and studying them in those terms. So I'm just going to give one example.
-
4:46 - 4:51It's a quote from a very famous paper from Pinker & Bloom in 1990,
-
4:51 - 4:56and they talk about the vocal-auditory channel having desirable features as a medium of communication:
-
4:56 - 5:01high-bandwidth; a serial interface; basic tools of a coding scheme;
-
5:01 - 5:05an inventory of distinguishable symbols and their concatenations.
-
5:05 - 5:09So we've got the language of information theory, of coding and decoding,
-
5:09 - 5:13scattered throughout this, and this is not just how people are thinking about it.
-
5:13 - 5:17It's also... You can see this in the methods that people employ, in the computational models and
-
5:17 - 5:19mathematical models that are build.
-
5:19 - 5:23But what people are looking at very much is coding systems,
-
5:23 - 5:26and how you start to combine symbols together to form
-
5:26 - 5:29more complex signals and so on and so forth.
-
5:29 - 5:34Very little work, actually, on the messy reality of language use out there in the world.
-
5:35 - 5:40If there's a central message to my book is that this agenda is a profound mistake.
-
5:40 - 5:44And I guess what I've tried to do in the book is
-
5:44 - 5:48to illustrate this is a profound mistake by taking pragmatic seriously, putting it front and center.
-
5:48 - 5:53This is what we're doing with language; this is what we're doing in communication in general.
-
5:53 - 5:56And showing that you can actually answer all the big questions you might want to ask
-
5:56 - 5:59about language evolution by taking pragmatics seriously.
-
5:59 - 6:06So why do only humans have language? Where are the points a continuity and discontinuity with other species?
-
6:06 - 6:11How do languages evolve the very structural properties that make them languages?
-
6:11 - 6:16All these questions get good answers if we start to take pragmatics seriously.
-
6:16 - 6:22I can't go into all that in one talk. What I'm going to do today is to talk about one of those questions,
-
6:22 - 6:28which is the relationship between non-human primate communication and human communication,
-
6:28 - 6:33the similarities and differences between them. And that will actually lead us to an explanation of
-
6:33 - 6:37—or part of an explanation— of why only humans have language.
-
6:37 - 6:43So let's get into a bit more detail. Actually, this is probably a good point for me to stress that
-
6:43 - 6:46I'm actually quite happy to take questions as we go along.
-
6:46 - 6:51I've come from research where that's the norm and I find that's quite a nice way
-
6:51 - 6:56for the speaker to know where the audience are. So please stick your hands up if you have any questions.
-
6:56 - 7:00OK, so let's go into a bit more detail on what the code-model communication is.
-
7:00 - 7:05One way of thinking about it is with what's called the conduit metaphor.
-
7:05 - 7:11You have this package, this thing that you put into a package, and then you send it along
-
7:11 - 7:14a conduit where it gets unwrapped at the other end.
-
7:14 - 7:18It's a way of thinking about how communication works in the first place.
-
7:18 - 7:23And we see this metaphor in our everyday language: "send me your ideas", "get your message across".
-
7:23 - 7:27Expressions like these are all employing this conduit metaphor.
-
7:28 - 7:31Another way of thinking about communication, a very famous way,
-
7:31 - 7:35is Shannon & Weaver's Information Theory. The idea here is
-
7:35 - 7:39that as information which gets encoded by some encoding algorithm,
-
7:39 - 7:44and then it gets transmitted, maybe some noise into the situation here,
-
7:44 - 7:48and then at this end it gets decoded by some decoding algorithm.
-
7:48 - 7:53And if the encoding algorithm the decoding algorithm are appropriately calibrated to one another,
-
7:53 - 7:58then what comes out one end is the same as what went in at the other end,
-
7:58 - 8:01and we can say communication has been successful.
-
8:03 - 8:08There's actually a plus sign here, though it's not strictly a sort of an equation
-
8:08 - 8:12(if you add these two up you get this). But you can probably see how
-
8:12 - 8:16if you're thinking about communication in these terms you end up with
-
8:16 - 8:21what I'm calling "natural codes"... And these are essentially pairs of associations;
-
8:21 - 8:24so you have an association between a state the world and a signal,
-
8:24 - 8:28and then an association between a signal and a response.
-
8:28 - 8:32And if those associations are matched up to one another, you can say we've got
-
8:32 - 8:36some sort communication system. So this is one natural code; this could be another natural code.
-
8:36 - 8:40And natural codes are perfectly good ways to think about many instances of communication in
-
8:40 - 8:43the natural world. It's how computers communicate, but is also,
-
8:43 - 8:47I think, the best way to describe all sorts of natural communication systems,
-
8:47 - 8:51from bacteria through insects, animals, and so on and so forth.
-
8:53 - 8:57The problem is... OK, before I move on to the problem...
-
8:58 - 9:03This is kind of stressing the point I was making earlier, that in language evolution
-
9:03 - 9:07were very much at the moment thinking about communication in terms of natural codes, so
-
9:07 - 9:12a BBS [Behavioral and Brain Sciences] paper, 2009, Nicholas Evans and Steve Levinson:
-
9:12 - 9:15"... those interested in the evolution of the biological preconditions for language
-
9:15 - 9:18have been looking in the wrong place"
-
9:18 - 9:22—I agree with them—"Instead of looking at the pragmatics of communicative exchange,
-
9:22 - 9:25they've been focused on the syntax and combinatorics".
-
9:25 - 9:27So that's where we are at the moment.
-
9:27 - 9:31We're looking at these codes and the combining of these codes in various ways.
-
9:31 - 9:35This is Wittgenstein on the left, and Paul Grice,
-
9:35 - 9:39who's often seen as a founder of pragmatics as a discipline.
-
9:39 - 9:45I like this slide because of the way they seem to be critically looking at each other
-
9:45 - 9:49Which kind of underlines one of the points both of them wanted to make
-
9:49 - 9:53—or at least Wittgenstein at one point of his career wanted to make—
-
9:53 - 9:59which is that communication is not as simple is this.. Actually, you know,
-
9:59 - 10:02it's very tempting, it's very attractive to look at languages
-
10:02 - 10:05and to try to make them fit this box of natural codes;
-
10:05 - 10:09to cut them up into digital components, and so on and so forth.
-
10:11 - 10:13But that doesn't work it turns out.
-
10:13 - 10:20And reality is undeterminancy... The fact that what I say is not the same as what I mean
-
10:20 - 10:23is actually not just the messy things on the edges.
-
10:23 - 10:25It's pervasive. It's everywhere.
-
10:25 - 10:30This is the point that both of these philosophers wanted to make.
-
10:30 - 10:34And we can see it (I'm not going to go deep into the philosophy) but we can see
-
10:34 - 10:39several simple examples just here. So, the most trivial example is to say, well, what's "that" here?
-
10:39 - 10:42We have these deictic expressions in languages.
-
10:42 - 10:47Pronouns, he/she and so on, and other examples.
-
10:47 - 10:52This here... Is this "bank" as in the side to the river or is it a financial institution?
-
10:52 - 10:59We don't know. This could mean "dinner", could mean "run away", it could mean
-
10:59 - 11:04"Look at the cute fluffy bunny"... It could mean all sorts of things.
-
11:04 - 11:09And in this one here Peter's answer (sorry if you cant see)
-
11:09 - 11:12Mary says, "Would you like to join us for dinner?"
-
11:12 - 11:14and Peter replies, "I ate earlier".
-
11:14 - 11:19And Peter's response doesn't actually answer Mary's question directly.
-
11:19 - 11:24He has not answered the question. Yet we all know and Mary knows what he's getting at.
-
11:24 - 11:28Now, the point I'm making here is not the trivial and obvious one,
-
11:28 - 11:32that there's ambiguity in language –we all know that, nobody's going to deny that.
-
11:32 - 11:38The point is that, as a code, as something to make communication possible in the first place,
-
11:38 - 11:42languages are not very good. In fact, they're quite hopeless.
-
11:42 - 11:46If all you've got is the code, if that's all, you don't know what this means,
-
11:46 - 11:51you don't know what this mean, in general don't know what any of this means on its own.
-
11:51 - 11:56So, to go back and think about the natural codes that made communication possible
-
11:56 - 11:58in that information-theoretic way.
-
11:58 - 12:02Communication can be said to exist if you have those pairs associations.
-
12:02 - 12:04That's simply not true here.
-
12:04 - 12:10If you just have a code, the linguistic code, you don't have communication, not yet.
-
12:10 - 12:16So taking these facts seriously, pragmatics has developed a different way of thinking
-
12:16 - 12:17about communication.
-
12:17 - 12:21Well, I've said "a" —there are probably several different proposals out there.
-
12:21 - 12:27I think the clearest one comes from Dan Sperber and Deirdre Wilson's Relevance Theory.
-
12:30 - 12:34And the label they used to contrast their way of thinking about
-
12:34 - 12:38communication with the code model... So they coined the term "code model", and they
-
12:38 - 12:42contrasted it with what they call the "ostensive-inferential model".
-
12:42 - 12:45A slightly cumbersome phrase, but it does capture what they're trying to describe.
-
12:45 - 12:52And the idea is that we're providing evidence... When we talk we're providing evidence and
-
12:52 - 12:56what we are providing evidence for is intentions.
-
12:56 - 12:59And more precisely, those intentions are what we call
-
12:59 - 13:02"communicative intention" and "informative intention".
-
13:02 - 13:08So, informative intention is my intention that you come to believe something.
-
13:08 - 13:12So if I say, "There is cake for dinner", I want you to believe that there is cake for dinner.
-
13:12 - 13:18That's my intention. I want to change your mental state so that you now you think that
-
13:18 - 13:20there is going to be cake for dinner.
-
13:20 - 13:24A communicative intention is my intention that you recognize that I have
-
13:24 - 13:26an informative intention in the first place.
-
13:26 - 13:33So: I intend that you understand that I intend that you understand that there is cake for dinner.
-
13:33 - 13:41Now, that sounds complex. But... —I'm certainly not going to go into all the details
-
13:41 - 13:46because wed be here all week— but when you get into the details of
-
13:46 - 13:51Relevance Theory, this account—this way of thinking about communications—starts
-
13:51 - 13:56to deal seriously with the philosophical issues that Grice and Wittgenstein and plenty of others
-
13:56 - 14:00were addressing or were raising, excuse me.
-
14:00 - 14:06A more simple way, without getting in all the jargon, a kind of the simplest way of thinking about
-
14:06 - 14:09what's going on here is: we're expressing two intentions:
-
14:09 - 14:15one is what I'm trying to communicate, and the other is the fact that I'm trying to communicate.
-
14:15 - 14:19So: "what am I trying to say" and "am I trying to say anything at all?"
-
14:19 - 14:23This is not just an account of linguistic communication but communication in general.
-
14:23 - 14:29So what's the difference between this point, which is direct and very clearly directing toward Clark,
-
14:29 - 14:35and this point here, where I'm looking at my watch and the fact that I am pointing is incidental.
-
14:35 - 14:38One of these is communicative and the other one is not.
-
14:38 - 14:41So one of them is expressing a communicative intention, and the other is not.
-
14:41 - 14:45That's the need for the communicative intention there.
-
14:45 - 14:48And then once that you recognize that somebody has a communicative intention
-
14:48 - 14:53you can go about the challenge of identifying the content of the informative intention,
-
14:53 - 14:54of this half here.
-
14:56 - 14:59And as I said, this is not just linguistic –we see this all times.
-
14:59 - 15:03Pointing is one example, but we also shrug, we do all sorts of things with our bodies,
-
15:03 - 15:08and when we do we do them, we do them in stylized and exaggerated ways, and in doing so make it
-
15:08 - 15:11apparent to our intended audience that we're trying to communicate with them
-
15:11 - 15:14and what it is we're trying to communicate.
-
15:14 - 15:17Here is one example: I was in a pub some weeks ago, standing at the bar with a friend,
-
15:17 - 15:20we we're both facing that way, the bar is here,
-
15:20 - 15:24and I had my note in one hand and my other hand just here.
-
15:24 - 15:29And my friend had just ordered some chips, and they'd arrived, they had just been given to him,
-
15:29 - 15:35so they're situated just here. And were chatting away, and I, with my hand, I just went like this,
-
15:35 - 15:36I don't know if you can all see that,
-
15:36 - 15:41so I was chatting away and I went did this, in a deliberate and stylized way.
-
15:41 - 15:42Made this gesture with my hand.
-
15:42 - 15:45And he just said Yes. And I took a chip and ate it.
-
15:45 - 15:49Now... we move our hands all the time, right?,
-
15:49 - 15:54but there's something about the stylized and exaggerated way in which I did that,
-
15:54 - 15:56which revealed to my friend that,
-
15:56 - 16:00a) I wanted to communicate with him, and b) what it was I wanted to communicate.
-
16:00 - 16:04This is not something you can capture with a natural code.
-
16:04 - 16:08We didn't have any convention associated with this expression and
-
16:08 - 16:12the idea "Can I have a chip?" This is just something that's created on the fly.
-
16:12 - 16:17As said, we shrug our shoulders, we do all sorts of things. This is ostensive communication.
-
16:18 - 16:24So what we have here is two ways of thinking about the very possibility of communication in the first place.
-
16:24 - 16:27On the one hand we have the code model, and the code model is defined
-
16:27 - 16:30by the fact that is made possible by associations.
-
16:30 - 16:38So if you have an organism able to make associations with the state the world and with some behavior,
-
16:38 - 16:42and perhaps with the observations of the world and some reaction,
-
16:42 - 16:46then you can have communication in the code-model type of way.
-
16:46 - 16:48We see this all over the natural world.
-
16:48 - 16:51On the other hand, you have this other type of communication,
-
16:51 - 16:54which is about expressing and recognizing intentions.
-
16:54 - 16:57And this is made possible—what defines it as a type of communication—
-
16:57 - 17:01is the fact that is a type of meta-psychology,
-
17:01 - 17:04is a type of manipulating others' minds,
-
17:04 - 17:09and mind-reading and manipulation. So, as a speaker, I'm trying to
-
17:09 - 17:14change your mental state right now. I'm manipulating your minds and you are trying to read my mental states.
-
17:14 - 17:17I have intentions and you're trying to read them.
-
17:17 - 17:21Made possible by our mechanisms of meta-psychology.
-
17:21 - 17:24And the difference here... I want to stress that the difference here
-
17:24 - 17:27is not one of degree; it's one of kind.
-
17:27 - 17:31And a way to make that graphic is to contrast it with an entirely different domain,
-
17:31 - 17:37namely locomotion. Flying and walking are two different types of locomotion.
-
17:37 - 17:42But we don't want to say that flying is some sort of enhanced form of walking.
-
17:42 - 17:49They're the same sort of thing, they're locomotion, but they're totally different ways
-
17:49 - 17:51of going about it, a difference in kind.
-
17:51 - 17:55Similarly, ostensive communication and code mode communication
-
17:55 - 17:57are differences in kind.
-
18:03 - 18:07So where does language fit into this distinction?
-
18:07 - 18:12It's a very assumption to make, a common assumption, that with linguistic communication
-
18:12 - 18:17what we're dealing with is a system which is really, at bottom, it's a code.
-
18:17 - 18:22And then on top of it you plug in all this meta-psychology, this pragmatics,
-
18:22 - 18:25and then you get language.
-
18:27 - 18:31Many people, both those inside linguistics and those outside,
-
18:31 - 18:35have said that, sometimes linguists have "physics envy".
-
18:35 - 18:40So they look at physics with this world where they can cut things up into precise things that are
-
18:40 - 18:44clearly identifiable. And they try to do the same thing with language, so
-
18:44 - 18:48you've got these individual phonemes and they are distinct from each other,
-
18:48 - 18:52and you can do the same thing for syntax and it goes to semantics and so on and so forth.
-
18:52 - 18:58And so the object of study for linguistics becomes –well, in addition, the object to study
-
18:58 - 19:02for linguistics are the languages themselves, the linguistic code.
-
19:02 - 19:06And so it's very easy to think that this is really what linguistic communication is about,
-
19:06 - 19:11is a type of communication made possible by associations—i.e. a code model—
-
19:11 - 19:17and then the meta-psychology, the pragmatics is the bonus, that's what makes it more expressively powerful.
-
19:17 - 19:21The reality is exactly the other way around. This common assumption is upside down.
-
19:21 - 19:24What's going on here, in linguistic communication,
-
19:24 - 19:29is that our communication is made possible by ostention, inference, meta-psychology.
-
19:29 - 19:33And then on top of that, what we've done is creating a linguistic code
-
19:33 - 19:37which allows us to be much more expressive, and more precise than we otherwise could be.
-
19:37 - 19:41So I can point to things in this room, but with language I can point to things
-
19:41 - 19:45remote in time and space, and I do that because I've got these tools, what
-
19:45 - 19:49we call the linguistic code, the conventions that allow me to do that.
-
19:49 - 19:56It's vital that our terminology reflects this; the difference between the sort of codes
-
19:56 - 20:01that are making ostensive communication more powerful and the natural code we had earlier.
-
20:01 - 20:06So natural codes make communication possible –that's the point I was making earlier.
-
20:06 - 20:09The linguistic code, on the other hand, is a different type of code.
-
20:09 - 20:14It's a type of code that makes a different type of communication, ostensive communication,
-
20:14 - 20:17more powerful. So I use this label: conventional codes.
-
20:17 - 20:22The linguistic code is a conventional code. It makes another type of communication—ostensive communication—
-
20:22 - 20:25more powerful than otherwise would be.
-
20:31 - 20:35OK, so now we understand what language is.
-
20:35 - 20:41Languages are conventional codes designed to make a type
-
20:41 - 20:45of communication more expressively powerful than otherwise would be.
-
20:45 - 20:49And with that thought in mind we can be very clear about what it is
-
20:49 - 20:51we're trying to explain the origins and evolution of.
-
20:51 - 20:56And we can boil this down to two things: on the one hand, we need to explain
-
20:56 - 21:00how we evolved the social-cognitive mechanisms that make ostensive communication
-
21:00 - 21:06possible in first place. That's one challenge. And the other challenge is to explain
-
21:06 - 21:10the creation, the cultural evolution of the conventional code itself.
-
21:10 - 21:14How, when we're interacting with each other, do we create these codes, converge upon
-
21:14 - 21:18shared meanings for those codes. And how do they change in the way they're used
-
21:18 - 21:21in interaction, passed between generations, to come to take the
-
21:21 - 21:24structural features that we associate with languages.
-
21:24 - 21:29They're really, to my mind, the two big questions for evolutionary linguistics.
-
21:29 - 21:31I'm going to talk in the rest of the talk about number one.
-
21:31 - 21:36Number two is where I think cultural attraction has a big role to play, and it's a very exciting
-
21:36 - 21:40area for research, but I'm not going to talk about that today. I'm going to focus
-
21:40 - 21:42for the rest of the talk on number one.
-
21:45 - 21:51There's a whole body of research looking at, comparing the cognitive abilities
-
21:51 - 21:58of humans, in particular human children, with those of our primate relatives, particularly chimpanzees.
-
22:00 - 22:05Then immediately, when I look at this literature I see a bit of... it's a challenge to comparison,
-
22:05 - 22:10when we look at it from the pragmatic perspective.
-
22:10 - 22:15In pragmatics we have a rich body of theory, we've defined this thing called ostensive communication.
-
22:15 - 22:19It's a very central idea about how human communication works.
-
22:19 - 22:23And people looking at non-human primate communication certainly recognize the
-
22:23 - 22:26importance of pragmatics –there's no question of that.
-
22:26 - 22:31The idea that intentions are critical is central to that literature.
-
22:31 - 22:35But what people have been studying for the most part is not this,
-
22:35 - 22:39but something else that is called intentional communication.
-
22:39 - 22:45The question is, well, are these the same thing? If not, how do they differ?
-
22:48 - 22:51And I think they're different things.
-
22:51 - 22:56When people look for intentional communication in the primate literature,
-
22:56 - 22:59there's a whole bunch of different criteria that are used,
-
22:59 - 23:03sometimes consistently, sometimes inconsistently,
-
23:03 - 23:04between different studies.
-
23:04 - 23:08And sometimes that inconsistency is for good methodological reasons.
-
23:08 - 23:12It's easier to look for certain of these criteria in one domain,
-
23:12 - 23:16say in the vocal domain rather than in the gesture domain and so on.
-
23:16 - 23:22But anyway, the literature by and large tends to use some or all of these seven criteria
-
23:22 - 23:26as measures of intentional communication.
-
23:27 - 23:32And some of these might be stronger or weaker than others.
-
23:32 - 23:36Now, rather than going into a detailed discussion of these, what I want to bring attention to
-
23:36 - 23:39is that all of these are really about goal-directedness.
-
23:39 - 23:42They're about how the signal itself is used.
-
23:42 - 23:47So, is the signal used in a goal-directed way, in an intentional way?,
-
23:47 - 23:54or is it used in a more... less socially-sensitive way?, in a way that perhaps suggests,
-
23:54 - 23:57less meta-psychology involved?
-
23:59 - 24:04Now, thinking back to what ostensive communications is, ostensive communication is defined
-
24:04 - 24:08as the expression of intentions. So what intentions are doing here,
-
24:08 - 24:12they're the thing that is being expressed, they're what is expressed.
-
24:12 - 24:16I express my informative intentions and my communicative intentions.
-
24:16 - 24:20When I point in a stylized way rather than an incidental way, I'm expressing
-
24:20 - 24:22a communicative intention.
-
24:22 - 24:25Whereas what's been studied in the primate literature, it seems to me,
-
24:25 - 24:30is "how" signals are being produced: are they produced in an intentional way or not?
-
24:30 - 24:33So these are not quite the same thing.
-
24:33 - 24:39Having said that, you'll often see the language used in the literature conflating the two.
-
24:39 - 24:45So, these communicative intentions (this phrase) has a technical definition in pragmatics,
-
24:45 - 24:50is the thing that expresses the signaling signalhood, the fact that you're trying to communicate.
-
24:51 - 24:56But this paper is certainly very much talking about an intention to communicate,
-
24:56 - 24:58actually about this sort of thing.
-
24:58 - 25:02It is not obvious to me that these are the same things.
-
25:02 - 25:09What we need to look at is: Do we see the expression and recognition of informative and communicative intentions?
-
25:09 - 25:13That's what ostensive communication is at bottom.
-
25:13 - 25:16And so that's really the question we should be asking.
-
25:16 - 25:21And there's at least enough data out there for us to give us a tentative answer to this question so...
-
25:21 - 25:23That's where we're going now.
-
25:23 - 25:28So, the expression and the recognition of communicative intentions and informative intentions.
-
25:28 - 25:34We have a two-by-two grid and we can ask about both human children and about great apes.
-
25:36 - 25:39And first we're going to look at the expression of informative intention.
-
25:39 - 25:43An informative intention is an intention to manipulate a mental state.
-
25:43 - 25:47I have an intention to change your mental states right now
-
25:47 - 25:50about what informative attentions are, and so on and so forth.
-
25:50 - 25:53So how might we go about testing this in the lab?
-
25:53 - 25:54Here's one way.
-
25:54 - 26:00In this study, the children come into the lab and they play a game set up in various ways
-
26:00 - 26:05but the long made short of it is that the child is going to make a request off the adult
-
26:05 - 26:08for an object. In this case a ball.
-
26:08 - 26:13And then they're going to get the ball, but they're going get it in one of two different conditions.
-
26:13 - 26:17Either they're going to get it because the experimenter says, "Oh, you want the ball?, here's the ball" -everybody's happy.
-
26:17 - 26:25Or the experimenter says, "Oh, you want the paper? (or the elephant?), and then, accidentally, gives them the ball.
-
26:25 - 26:30So in this case the child has the material goal satisfied
-
26:30 - 26:37but if they have an informative intention, an intention to manipulate a mental state, that's actually not been satisfied,
-
26:37 - 26:42because the adult's mental state has not been changed in the way that the child so wished.
-
26:42 - 26:44Whereas in this case that has happened.
-
26:44 - 26:49And what we find is that children kick up a fuss in this situation, they start complaining.
-
26:49 - 26:52"No, you didn't understand"; "No, I want the ball"; "But you have the ball;"
-
26:52 - 26:55"but, but, but..." And you can see where this goes.
-
26:55 - 27:01The fact that they're complaining shows that their goals are not simply material, not simply to get the ball,
-
27:01 - 27:05but change the mental state of the adult, which in turn will get them the ball.
-
27:05 - 27:11So children understand, they have some understanding, of what an informative intention is,
-
27:11 - 27:16and are able to express it, and understand when that intention has been satisfied or not.
-
27:17 - 27:21Nobody's done the comparable experiment with great apes.
-
27:25 - 27:29Recognition of an informative intention... Well, actually, here nobody's done the experiment
-
27:29 - 27:31with great apes or with children.
-
27:31 - 27:35And the sort of experiment that could be done would be
-
27:35 - 27:41similar to the previous one I've just described, but perhaps with an observer and if that observer...
-
27:43 - 27:46Hold on, my thoughts have gone blank, sorry...
-
27:52 - 27:54Sorry --I have a mind blank.
-
28:00 - 28:02No, my mind's gone blank.
-
28:02 - 28:05Hopefully you're doing the work for me and you're on your own!
-
28:05 - 28:06Sorry?
-
28:06 - 28:07[...unintelligible...]
-
28:07 - 28:09--Yeah, maybe so yes
-
28:09 - 28:18[(...unintelligible...) the wrong thing is given and the observer says bad-bad-bad or something?]
-
28:19 - 28:21Good, good okay, yes twice! Coming back now...!
-
28:21 - 28:25So, let's say... Let's go back to the previous one...
-
28:29 - 28:33Let's say we're in this situation and then the child doesn't complain,
-
28:33 - 28:36or another adult—there are two adults—and this adult asks for the ball,
-
28:36 - 28:40gets the ball, even though they we're misunderstood.
-
28:40 - 28:44Does the observer say, "Hold on!!, something's not up, something's not right here..."?
-
28:44 - 28:49And if they do, they're recognizing that somebody else—namely this person—has an informative intention.
-
28:49 - 28:52Nobody's done that experiment with kids or with apes.
-
28:53 - 28:55So we don't know the answer to that.
-
28:55 - 29:01Let's look now at communicative intentions. Communicative intentions are intentions to make it
-
29:01 - 29:06apparent to your audience that you have an informative intention. It's signaling signalhood.
-
29:06 - 29:11Making apparent to somebody that you want to communicate with them in the first place.
-
29:14 - 29:18And the recognition of communicative intentions has been studied in several different ways.
-
29:18 - 29:22I think the clearest demonstration is in this paper. What happens here...
-
29:22 - 29:25(This is where the example of the point, the incidental point
-
29:25 - 29:28because I'm looking at my watch, and the direct point come from).
-
29:28 - 29:34In this study the children and the experimenter play a game and they
-
29:34 - 29:39play with his toys, and then the game comes to an end and they have to pack the toys away.
-
29:39 - 29:45And they do so. One of the toys is accidentally sort of left out somewhere else in the room.
-
29:45 - 29:51And the child is (...), and the experimenter points at the toy.
-
29:51 - 29:58And the experimenter either points at the toy in a very ostensive, deliberate, stylized way
-
29:58 - 30:01—i.e. with expression of communicative intention—
-
30:01 - 30:09like this, looking at the child. Or they point (they're still pointing) but they're looking at their watch.
-
30:09 - 30:12So, superficially similar behaviors but one expresses a communicative intention,
-
30:12 - 30:14the other one doesn't.
-
30:14 - 30:18And what happens is that children are far more likely to go and fetch the toy
-
30:18 - 30:22and put it away when the communicative intention has been expressed.
-
30:22 - 30:25So it seems that the children are able to recognize the communicative intention
-
30:25 - 30:28when is expressed by an adult.
-
30:29 - 30:32Again, not been done in great apes.
-
30:32 - 30:41[So what about meta communication and play (…unintelligible…) What about in another domain? —
-
30:41 - 30:45(….) multi component signals where part of it is what follows is going to be
-
30:45 - 30:49(...potentially informative...), which has been demonstrated in lots of studies?
-
30:50 - 30:51Right...
-
30:52 - 31:00Isn't that a signal about a signal? Isn't that a signal about "pay attention to what follows"?
-
31:02 - 31:07I don’t know the literature you’re referring to in enough detail, so I’d have to look at that
-
31:07 - 31:08to be able to answer the question.
-
31:09 - 31:13[(...Playouts....), you know, things like that… that all animals would engage in
-
31:13 - 31:18(…some kind of game and pay attention to signals…)] and what follows is going to be play]
-
31:18 - 31:21These things are akin to attention-getters I guess…
-
31:21 - 31:26[…and then you can think about multi-component signals (...) (...that later...) become informative in same way.]
-
31:27 - 31:31So it seems to me… I’m more familiar with the idea of attention-getters…
-
31:31 - 31:34that seems to be similar to what you’re pointing to.
-
31:34 - 31:38That seems describable to me in terms of a natural code.
-
31:38 - 31:45So you can form associations between those behaviors and a subsequent behavior,
-
31:45 - 31:48and hence you can say, well, this would be a natural code.
-
31:48 - 31:55What's going on here is that... The study I just described would be stronger if it wasn't pointing,
-
31:55 - 32:00if it was something that was.... uncontroversially could not have been said
-
32:00 - 32:07that any convention could have been formed. And that's really the Litmus test, right?
-
32:07 - 32:12So it's that... when I was in the pub with my friend and I tilted my hand...
-
32:12 - 32:19There's no pre-established convention or anything else there... When you do see... Yes?
-
32:19 - 32:28[unintelligible] Are (...) necessary? In the sense that, if you take a more continuous view of
-
32:28 - 32:33the evolution of signals or the evolution of meaning or the evolution of manipulation,
-
32:33 - 32:43arbitrariness is great, that was (X)'s criteria, but you can imagine pressures, structure,
-
32:43 - 32:49form-follows-function, function-follows-design criteria, things sound and look certain ways to be
-
32:49 - 32:56effective—efficacy—and it's nice to sort of say that humans are (...great...) because
-
32:56 - 33:03we can (...have arbitrary...) signals, but is that a necessary component of thinking about these intentional...
-
33:03 - 33:05No no, I'm not saying...
-
33:05 - 33:12I'm not trying to link arbitrariness to this distinction I'm trying to draw up here at the moment.
-
33:12 - 33:17What I'm saying is that the best way to test the true expression and
-
33:17 - 33:20recognition of communicative intentions is in a context where
-
33:20 - 33:25there's no way that you can say that this is a conventional code, a natural code of any sort.
-
33:25 - 33:28I'm interested in the question of how you test for these things,
-
33:28 - 33:31and the best way to do that would be in that way.
-
33:31 - 33:33Coming back to the attention-getters, I mean...
-
33:33 - 33:38Most of them seem to be iconic?, from my knowledge of them...
-
33:38 - 33:40It's conceivable that they don't have to be.
-
33:40 - 33:44But either way, they can be described in terms of a natural code.
-
33:44 - 33:45[I agree with that.]
-
33:45 - 33:47Well, OK.
-
33:49 - 33:53OK, finally, the expression of communicative intention:
-
33:53 - 34:00expressing the fact that you want to communicate with somebody else.
-
34:00 - 34:05Now, how are you going to go about testing this in children? (Well, in great apes I really don't know),
-
34:05 - 34:08but in children is much straight forward.
-
34:08 - 34:12A few years ago, I spent some time in Mike Tomasello's lab and
-
34:12 - 34:15we looked into something that is not strictly speaking the expression of
-
34:15 - 34:20communicative intentions but it shows exactly the same sort of thing.
-
34:20 - 34:24We were interested in something called "hidden authorship".
-
34:24 - 34:27With hidden authorship –this is providing a stimulus for someone
-
34:27 - 34:30but hiding the fact that you're actually proving it for them.
-
34:30 - 34:34Imagine you are at a polite dinner party and you want some more wine but
-
34:34 - 34:37is impolite for you to ask your host for more wine directly.
-
34:37 - 34:43So you wait until he or she has turned their back and then you move your empty wine glass to
-
34:43 - 34:47somewhere conspicuous in the middle of the table, and you wait for them to turn around and
-
34:47 - 34:49the see the wine glass and they fill it up.
-
34:49 - 34:53So you provided a stimulus for someone but you hidden the fact that is for them.
-
34:53 - 34:56And this is interesting because...
-
34:57 - 35:01it expresses an intention, or is evidence of an intention which has
-
35:01 - 35:06the same relationship to an informative intention that communicative intention does.
-
35:06 - 35:07It just is a negative.
-
35:07 - 35:09So rather than,
-
35:09 - 35:12"I intend that you understand that I have an informative intention",
-
35:12 - 35:16"I intend that you don't understand that I have an informative intention towards you".
-
35:16 - 35:18Otherwise, it is the same sort of thing.
-
35:18 - 35:22So we wanted to test whether children could hide authorship.
-
35:22 - 35:24So here is how we went about it.
-
35:24 - 35:28The first thing I should say is that we did it with 3- and 4 year-olds, quite young kids.
-
35:28 - 35:32This kind is quite a bit older but that's because this video is from the pilot study, but
-
35:32 - 35:34is representative of what happened.
-
35:34 - 35:39So... there's Experimenter 1 here, and the child, this is Experimenter 2.
-
35:39 - 35:44Experimenter 1 and the child come into the room first and they find in the middle of the room this
-
35:44 - 35:49box which has four hose in it, and you can see from the hose what kind of objects belong in there.
-
35:49 - 35:53There's a hat, there's car and there's a ball, and so on and so forth.
-
35:53 - 35:57And, "Oh, I like the hiding and finding game, we need to find these objects that
-
35:57 - 36:00are hidden around the room so let's go and find them".
-
36:00 - 36:02So the experimenter and the child find the objects.
-
36:02 - 36:06And in that way the child -excuse me, they find the objects and then the experimenter says,
-
36:06 - 36:11"Oh, experimenter 2 is coming along as well and she really likes the hiding-finding game and so
-
36:11 - 36:14we need to put these object back where we found them so she can have a go herself".
-
36:14 - 36:18They go about that. So the child now knows where all the objects are.
-
36:18 - 36:21Then the child sits down just here, next to Experimenter 1.
-
36:21 - 36:26Experimenter 2 comes in and is going to play the hiding-and-finding game.
-
36:26 - 36:30Before I explain exactly what she does, is worth stressing that the ball that goes in here
-
36:30 - 36:34is hidden just behind this barrier, just next to where the child sits down.
-
36:34 - 36:37This barrier here is the same as this barrier here.
-
36:37 - 36:41And Experimenter 2 comes in and says, "Oh, is the hiding-and-finding game,
-
36:41 - 36:45I really like the game," and then she says "but" and she says
-
36:45 - 36:48one of two different things depending on condition:
-
36:48 - 36:52She either says, "Oh, I really don't like it if I can't complete it,"
-
36:52 - 36:56in which case she's given the child reasons to help her, or she says:
-
36:56 - 36:59"But I really don't like it if anyone helps me complete it,"
-
36:59 - 37:03so now she's forbidden the child to help her find the object.
-
37:03 - 37:07So then she goes around and finds a couple of the objects.
-
37:07 - 37:11She's already found the hat as you can see, and then there's a couple of others she can't find them.
-
37:11 - 37:13"Oh, where's the ball, I cant find it, I'm looking everywhere."
-
37:13 - 37:17She spends plenty of time with her back to the child so the child can do
-
37:17 - 37:20various things to help her without her knowing.
-
37:20 - 37:22And the question is what the childs going to do.
-
37:22 - 37:25So keep your eye on this child here and what he does with ball.
-
37:32 - 37:36So he takes the ball, moves it in front, and the experimenter turns around and says,
-
37:36 - 37:39"Oh, there's the ball why didn't I see it earlier, it was always there in clear view",
-
37:39 - 37:41and the child is very happy.
-
37:41 - 37:47This is a 7-year-old child as I said; you do it with younger kids is not quite as clean as this [laughs]
-
37:47 - 37:53They do things like: Ahem! [laughs] and, in various ways, try to have it both ways.
-
37:53 - 37:58But the fact that they want to have it both ways, shows that they understand the difference between
-
37:58 - 38:03an informative intention—providing the stimulus for someone—and a communicative intention:
-
38:03 - 38:06the fact that youre trying to communicate with them.
-
38:06 - 38:11We find very clear differences in both in 3- and 5-year olds
-
38:11 - 38:18in terms of the number of times they suppress that intention in various trials.
-
38:21 - 38:25OK, so here's our provisional conclusions... Go ahead.
-
38:25 - 38:29[Oh, after you do your provisional conclusions...]
-
38:29 - 38:32OK. Is it going to be about this slide, is it? or...
-
38:32 - 38:35[It's about this experiment as a whole, so...]
-
38:35 - 38:37Go now
-
38:37 - 38:38[No (...unintelligible...)]
-
38:38 - 38:44My provisional conclusion is that children are ostensive communicators.
-
38:44 - 38:51So there isn't any of these cells that isn't filled in and you were right to raise the point that
-
38:51 - 38:59for this here perhaps could be done without pointing, with some other behavior
-
38:59 - 39:04But it's starting to look as that the answer for children here is going to be Yes.
-
39:04 - 39:08The answer for great apes we don't know and there are clear methodological challenges to
-
39:08 - 39:11doing these sorts of studies with chimps, I mean I see that.
-
39:11 - 39:16Nevertheless, when I've spoken to relevant experts of chimpanzee communication and cognition,
-
39:16 - 39:21they expressed a great deal of skepticism that chimps are going to pass these sorts of studies.
-
39:21 - 39:27Now, that's an entirely provisional conclusion, could be overturn by data, of course it could.
-
39:27 - 39:30But my provisional conclusion...
-
39:30 - 39:34–well, I should add also, it's also interesting that the studies haven't been done.
-
39:34 - 39:39Although some of them... The hidden-authorship study is not at all clear how you'd do that,
-
39:39 - 39:41big methodological challenges.
-
39:41 - 39:47But the first study—about when the ball... and receiving the right object
-
39:47 - 39:50for the wrong reason and so on and so forth—
-
39:50 - 39:55that is perhaps amountable, but nobody seems to have done it.
-
39:55 - 40:01And I do wonder if the reason why nobody's done that is because
-
40:01 - 40:05researchers are skeptical that chimps are going to pass it and if you get negative
-
40:05 - 40:08results is perhaps difficult to interpret, difficult to publish...
-
40:08 - 40:12Maybe little motivation to pursuing such an experiment if you're skeptical about
-
40:12 - 40:17the possible outcome. Entirely provisional. Totally, these conclusions could be overturned by data,
-
40:17 - 40:21but for now, it seems to me that the data suggest that non-human primates
-
40:21 - 40:24are not communicating in an ostensive, inferential way.
-
40:25 - 40:30[I don't know if you have maybe just 30 seconds, depending upon your time...
-
40:30 - 40:36(...unintelligible...)
-
40:36 - 40:39... but the division you spoke of…
-
40:41 - 40:48You’re looking at the social aspects… of the subject here, right?
-
40:49 - 40:55(...of...) the ostensive and the informative things… You said (...your work is going to look...) at cultural…
-
40:56 - 41:03Beyond a certain age—in humans of course—culture is very strong.]
-
41:03 - 41:05Of course, yes.
-
41:05 - 41:15[... And whether or not a teenager or an adult is going to do something that a child
-
41:15 - 41:24might do is a question… And how they’re going to do it, is certainly a question….
-
41:24 - 41:27So my basic question is…
-
41:30 - 41:33What is your justification for
-
41:33 - 41:42separating the social from the cultural… And perhaps if you have time (….),
-
41:42 - 41:51could you give us a minute of what that cultural research is that you’re doing, on this area?]
-
41:51 - 41:56I'm not trying to separate social from cultural, that's the first thing to say.
-
41:56 - 42:01What I am separating out is the social-cognitive mechanisms—cognitive mechanisms—
-
42:01 - 42:05that make ostensive communication possible in the first place.
-
42:05 - 42:10So they're mechanisms of meta-psychology which (...gives rise...) to these sorts of behaviors...
-
42:10 - 42:16[My question is how can you, particularly with teenagers and adults,
-
42:16 - 42:22take out the strong cultural influences (...)?]
-
42:22 - 42:23I'm not trying to.
-
42:23 - 42:31[You're not? So if you had time (...) to talk a little bit about the
-
42:31 - 42:35cultural aspects of your research in this area]
-
42:35 - 42:41I still have three slides to go... Can I do that in the question session?
-
42:41 - 42:45[OK, so that'd be my first question] [laughs]
-
42:48 - 42:52So I've made this dichotomy earlier between two different ways of thinking about the
-
42:52 - 42:55possibility of communication.
-
42:55 - 42:59So, ostension and inference on the one hand, which provisionally for now I'm going to say
-
42:59 - 43:04only seems to be present in humans... And on the other hand code-model communication.
-
43:04 - 43:07So if it is the case that non-human primates don't communicate ostensibly
-
43:07 - 43:10then it should be the case that they communicate using natural codes.
-
43:10 - 43:13But we should check that. Let's look at the data here.
-
43:13 - 43:16Do they communicate using natural codes?
-
43:16 - 43:21It's certainly true that great apes gestural communication is accepted to be intentional.
-
43:21 - 43:24And there's a live debate in the literature at the moment about the origins of
-
43:24 - 43:27the the codes that are being used.
-
43:27 - 43:32On the one hand, you have researchers arguing that processes of ontogenetic ritualization
-
43:32 - 43:37can give rise to these codes; others saying that there's more of a perhaps innate
-
43:37 - 43:40or, in some ways, species-wide repertoire.
-
43:40 - 43:44The point I want to make is that either way, what we're looking at here is
-
43:44 - 43:47an argument about the origins of associations
-
43:47 - 43:52between states of the world and behaviors and between behaviors and responses.
-
43:52 - 43:54In other words, the origins of natural codes.
-
43:54 - 43:57So, they're not using the language of the natural codes,
-
43:57 - 44:00but they're talking about associations of certain types.
-
44:00 - 44:05That's pervasive through the discussions that are going on in this literature.
-
44:05 - 44:11Here is a quote: "We conducted naturalistic observations of wild East African chimpanzee...
-
44:11 - 44:15Our results indicate that chimpanzees are able to respond flexibly"
-
44:15 - 44:18Why did I put that quote there? I've no idea [laughs].
-
44:18 - 44:21That might be lost ignore that!
-
44:21 - 44:25It's kind of relevant but I don't know [...unintelligible...] the point I was trying to make.
-
44:25 - 44:29Oh yeah –this is why. OK, let me go back, now I know why...
-
44:29 - 44:32Sorry. Let's go down to here.
-
44:32 - 44:36OK, so there's the natural code. What's particularly interesting about these natural codes
-
44:36 - 44:38is that they seem to be used in a very flexible way.
-
44:38 - 44:42So we can describe for example bacterial communication in terms of a natural code
-
44:42 - 44:49and that'd be a very fixed natural code governed by various, relatively simple, mechanisms.
-
44:51 - 44:54But it seems to be more flexible in chimpanzees, so there's the question of
-
44:54 - 44:57where that flexibility comes from.
-
44:57 - 44:59And the natural answer would be some sort of Theory of Mind,
-
44:59 - 45:02meta-psychological abilities of some sort.
-
45:02 - 45:08Obviously, as I'm sure many or most or all of you are aware,
-
45:08 - 45:12there are live debates about exactly what the extent of
-
45:12 - 45:16such abilities might be in chimpanzees, but it seems to be... It might not be a full-blown
-
45:16 - 45:20Theory of Mind but some sort of awareness of the goals of others
-
45:20 - 45:23that does seem to be present in some of our primate relatives.
-
45:23 - 45:27So the answer to the question here is a kind of "Yes, but..."
-
45:27 - 45:32Yes, they seem to use natural codes, but they're natural codes which
-
45:32 - 45:37are being made more expressively powerful by forms of meta-psychology.
-
45:37 - 45:40This, interestingly, appears to be the very opposite of
-
45:40 - 45:43what we actually see in linguistic communication.
-
45:43 - 45:50So linguistic communication is made possible by mechanisms of meta-psychology,
-
45:50 - 45:54which allow us to shrug, to point, to do all these things that we do non-verbally.
-
45:54 - 45:59And then it's made more precise and expressively powerful by mechanisms of association;
-
45:59 - 46:02by the fact that we can create these conventions.
-
46:02 - 46:04Great-ape communication seems to be entirely the other way up.
-
46:04 - 46:07It's made possible by these natural codes,
-
46:07 - 46:10but then it's used in a particularly flexible way which makes it richer
-
46:10 - 46:16than other natural codes out there in the natural world because of some forms of meta-psychology.
-
46:16 - 46:22So, how would we tell the difference between these two different types of communication?
-
46:22 - 46:26Well, if you have a set of associations made more powerful by meta-psychology,
-
46:26 - 46:35then what you should expect to see is some sort of more finite set of prototypes of some sort...
-
46:35 - 46:39that's the base of associations, but then is used in more flexible ways.
-
46:39 - 46:43And it seems to me that the quote from that paper and other papers
-
46:43 - 46:46seem to be pointing in that direction.
-
46:46 - 46:52Papers that are looking at cataloguing what non-human primate communication systems look like
-
46:52 - 46:55are converging upon this sort of conclusion.
-
46:55 - 46:59On the other hand, if you have a system made possible by meta-psychology,
-
46:59 - 47:01and then made more powerful by associations,
-
47:01 - 47:05then essentially anything goes! If it's made possibly by meta-psychology,
-
47:05 - 47:09then you can create new signals at will.
-
47:09 - 47:14You can have associations that can be used in all sorts of ways.
-
47:14 - 47:19And you have the one-off use of novel behaviors like the twisting of my wrist for communicative ends.
-
47:19 - 47:22This seems to be what we see in language.
-
47:24 - 47:29These points have important implications for how we think about continuity and discontinuity
-
47:29 - 47:31in human communication and language.
-
47:31 - 47:35As said earlier, it's a common assumption in evolutionary linguistics,
-
47:35 - 47:39or in linguistics in general and in evolutionary linguistics,
-
47:39 - 47:43that the code is the thing that makes everything possible and the pragmatics
-
47:43 - 47:47goes on top as if the messy stuff goes on top to make it more powerful.
-
47:47 - 47:51And you can see that... This is James Hurfords two books, 2007, 2012.
-
47:51 - 47:56"We may see in alarm calls a skeletal version of our own shared codes"
-
47:56 - 48:00–so the continuity there, between the monkeys calls and human languages.
-
48:00 - 48:04"It seems quite plausible that the earlier precursors of language were much more,
-
48:04 - 48:07perhaps entirely, coding-decoding in nature".
-
48:07 - 48:10So language starts as a code model then you have the pragmatics on later.
-
48:10 - 48:13I think this is a big mistake.
-
48:13 - 48:20The emphasis on continuity here is taking the Darwinian lesson that form changes very gradually,
-
48:20 - 48:23but then applying it to function too.
-
48:23 - 48:30It's a bit like saying, Well, flying is a very powerful form of locomotion, walking is less powerful,
-
48:30 - 48:35Darwin tells us these things change gradually, so one must have evolved from the other.
-
48:35 - 48:36That doesn't fly.
-
48:36 - 48:39The real continuity here is in social intelligence.
-
48:39 - 48:42So, non-human primate communication is made more expressively powerful by
-
48:42 - 48:45forms of meta-psychology.
-
48:45 - 48:50When they're made even more rich, they allow a whole new type of communication system:
-
48:50 - 48:55ostensive communication. When you start adding the layers, the recursive mind-reading layers,
-
48:55 - 49:01then from the total that was being used to make a natural code more powerful,
-
49:01 - 49:05you suddenly get a quite new form of communication: ostensive communication,
-
49:05 - 49:10which really opens the flood gates to all sorts of communicative richness.
-
49:11 - 49:13OK , let me wrap up.
-
49:13 - 49:20Human communication is ostensive and inferential. We're expressing and recognizing intentions;
-
49:20 - 49:22informative and communicative intentions.
-
49:22 - 49:27It's critical when we're thinking about the evolution of language to distinguish
-
49:27 - 49:29between natural codes and conventional codes.
-
49:29 - 49:32Natural codes make communication possible in the first place.
-
49:32 - 49:36Computers communicate in that way, bacteria do, and so on and so forth.
-
49:36 - 49:40Conventional codes do something quite different. They make an already-existing,
-
49:40 - 49:45different type of communication systems more powerful than otherwise would be.
-
49:47 - 49:51Something I didn't talk about in detail was that point number two from earlier.
-
49:51 - 49:53If we're going to look at cultural evolution of conventional codes,
-
49:53 - 49:59the right framework I think to do that, is cultural attraction.
-
50:01 - 50:05Non-human primate communication is probably using natural codes.
-
50:05 - 50:08That is a conclusion that could be overturned by more data.
-
50:08 - 50:16But it is made more expressive by some limited forms of meta-psychological abilities.
-
50:16 - 50:21What that tells us is that the continuity between non-human primates and humans
-
50:21 - 50:24is really in social intelligence.
-
50:24 - 50:27It goes from limited forms of mind-reading and manipulation to
-
50:27 - 50:32a form of mind-reading and manipulation where we're actually helping each other do that.
-
50:32 - 50:36I'm encouraging you to read my mind right now, and you're allowing me to
-
50:36 - 50:40manipulate your mental states. More generally, pragmatics
-
50:40 - 50:46—the messy reality of using language out there in communication in real-world language use—
-
50:46 - 50:50is solely neglected in language evolution research.
-
50:50 - 50:52Thank you very much for your time.
-
50:52 - 50:56[Applause]
-
51:03 - 51:08[Just if perhaps... 2 or 3 minutes to give an example of your research on
-
51:08 - 51:14that question which you call cultural attraction. I'd never heard that term before.]
-
51:14 - 51:20OK. The idea of cultural attraction is... The thing to explain...
-
51:21 - 51:26So, there are ... OK, two or three minutes is long enough.
-
51:28 - 51:31Culture consists of two types of things:
-
51:31 - 51:36mental representations and public expressions of those mental representations.
-
51:36 - 51:39Some mental representations are widely shared in the community and
-
51:39 - 51:44some are only shared sometimes. The ones that are widely shared are the ones we call culture.
-
51:44 - 51:48So we might all have similar ideas of, you know, God or whatever might be...
-
51:48 - 51:52And if we have similar versions of that mental representation we call it culture.
-
51:52 - 51:56The thing that needs explaining is why some mental representations are
-
51:56 - 52:00common in a population, some are not common. And...
-
52:03 - 52:07And I guess the key insight in cultural attraction theory is that
-
52:07 - 52:12as these mental representations and their public expressions are passed through a community...
-
52:12 - 52:17As I'm taking to you, I'm taking my mental representations, forming a public expression,
-
52:17 - 52:21and you're taking that public expression and forming your own mental representations.
-
52:21 - 52:24There's no guarantee that those two mental representations are the same and
-
52:24 - 52:27in fact our mechanisms of communication and cognition are actually
-
52:27 - 52:30going to manipulate them to fit them with our existing mental representation
-
52:30 - 52:32and so on and so forth...
-
52:32 - 52:38And those changes are often going to be common through a population.
-
52:38 - 52:41So you might change in a very similar way to many other people.
-
52:41 - 52:45And if many of us are making similar changes,
-
52:45 - 52:49then those mental representations tend to gravitate in certain directions and not in others.
-
52:49 - 52:51[...unintelligible...]
-
52:51 - 52:57Well, there are subtle though I think very important differences between the labels,
-
52:57 - 53:00which I'm not going to go into the details...
-
53:00 - 53:05[I understand that. I think we can stop there as far as I am concern, cause I understand.
-
53:05 - 53:09Do you know who (...is going to read...) on kin selection?]
-
53:09 - 53:20[...unintelligible...]
-
53:26 - 53:37[Taking your argument for Darwinian gradualism seriously, I actually have objections to your flight analogy
-
53:37 - 53:40(... that'd like to put as an aside...) (...)]
-
53:41 - 53:46Yes, yes, I realize that... It was more to make a point than to...
-
53:46 - 53:53[I understand... But so, the same concern applies more substantively to your conclusions for
-
53:53 - 53:56the very differences between the great apes and humans,
-
53:56 - 53:59which is: How do we get from here to there...?
-
53:59 - 54:05That is, if Theory of Mind abilities and social reasoning in general...
-
54:06 - 54:11appear progressively across apes and,
-
54:11 - 54:16presumably (...keeping in time...) across hominids, right?,
-
54:16 - 54:22then why do we get a reversal, why don't we see the same sort of emergence of
-
54:22 - 54:28communicative abilities in parallel with mind-reading abilities in, you know,
-
54:28 - 54:40co-extinct apes now rather than the reverse (...you claim...)? So, you're claiming that social cognition adds to the ability
-
54:40 - 54:47to manipulate the natural codes, but (...isn't the...) the driver of much of the behavior,
-
54:47 - 54:54and the reverse is true in humans. And I would say, well, why don't we see the two emerging...
-
54:54 - 54:59If what we see is more limited abilities in both extents in (...us...)
-
54:59 - 55:02and great apes, and if we're (...taking them into
-
55:02 - 55:08some winter into the past...) (...), then why the reversal? Wouldn't you expect to see, you know,
-
55:08 - 55:13according to Darwinian gradualism, wouldn't we expect to see the same kind of linear progression?
-
55:13 - 55:17That is, there's no half-a-wing problem there, you know.
-
55:17 - 55:20There's a little bit of a forelimb with some feathers on it, then there's a bit more
-
55:20 - 55:24and a bit more, and stops being a forelimb and starts being a wing and so on...]
-
55:24 - 55:32OK, good yes. So... In a way, the point where my analogy with locomotion and wings falls down is
-
55:32 - 55:37exactly where, how I want to answer the question. So, that analogy isn't perfect, I grant.
-
55:37 - 55:40You get into the details of ostensive communication... It's
-
55:40 - 55:45an intention that you understand I have an intention that you understand X.
-
55:45 - 55:50You don't get ostensive communication until all that apparatus is in place.
-
55:50 - 55:55There aren't... It doesn't seem to me that there are...
-
55:55 - 55:58It doesn't seem to me that there are partly ostensive forms of communication;
-
55:58 - 56:02you've got to have the whole apparatus in place in the first place.
-
56:02 - 56:08So you can build ever small sophisticated ways of reasoning about each others' minds.
-
56:08 - 56:13But once they... It's only once they start to become recursive in quite a rich way that you actually get
-
56:13 - 56:16ostensive communication happening
-
56:16 - 56:19[OK, so you have to have all of the selection for the mind-reading abilities coming from something else...]
-
56:19 - 56:24Yes, which would be some sort of Social Brain Hypothesis.]
-
56:24 - 56:29[So, good. Well, it's a Machiavellian intelligence argument with no communication in their (...)]
-
56:29 - 56:31Not in the first place.
-
56:31 - 56:35[(...) does necessarily depend upon your idea of gradualism?]
-
56:38 - 56:42Does what depend on my idea of gradualism?
-
56:42 - 56:45[Does your argument really depend on gradualism?]
-
56:45 - 56:47So...
-
56:47 - 56:56[I only ask that because I think there are lots of situations (...) where the edifice
-
56:56 - 57:00doesn't fall on (...) rise and fall (...on...) gradualism.]
-
57:00 - 57:04Oh, no, I'm not saying my argument rises or falls on gradualism But, you know, (...)
-
57:10 - 57:14[I found that really interesting and convincing.
-
57:14 - 57:17Although one thing that was left unstated, it was implicit,
-
57:17 - 57:21was why you think that testing these things in human children is important?
-
57:21 - 57:27And I'm wondering, you know, are there particular ages that you think are, you know...
-
57:27 - 57:31Do we have to push it back to the earliest point possible in order to
-
57:31 - 57:35provide the strongest test? Could you say some things about that?]
-
57:35 - 57:37The general motivation of that sort of...
-
57:37 - 57:40[... and what you think the research on the young kids tells us
-
57:40 - 57:42with respect to the evolution of language]
-
57:42 - 57:45It controls for other types of intelligence,
-
57:45 - 57:48in particular physical intelligence, intelligence with the physical world.
-
57:48 - 57:52So, children at about... —(...) knows better than I exactly at what sort of ages—
-
57:52 - 57:56but around 2 or 3 years of age, adult chimpanzees and young children
-
57:56 - 58:01have similar powers for understanding the physical world (...)
-
58:01 - 58:07but they seem to have very different powers with the social world. So you're controlling for that
-
58:07 - 58:12other general type of intelligence, when you're comparing their social intelligence.
-
58:12 - 58:16[And... could you say just a little bit more about that? Why is that important?]
-
58:16 - 58:21Oh, well, because let's say we did this on adults, or with teenagers or whatever. Then somebody
-
58:21 - 58:26could turn around and say, Well they're just generally more intelligent. So it's not the fact that,
-
58:26 - 58:29that there's any particularly social intelligence or
-
58:29 - 58:32particularly meta-psychological-community intelligence;
-
58:32 - 58:36it's just the general intelligence that's being applied to a particular problem at hand.
-
58:36 - 58:43You can control for that by dealing with humans that have similar powers in those regards.
-
58:50 - 58:50Go on
-
58:51 - 58:57[The argument you're making for a shift in terms of associative, ostensive (...)
-
58:57 - 59:02that characterize your argument with great apes and the reversal with humans,
-
59:02 - 59:07and particularly the notion that this is not gradual transition,
-
59:07 - 59:11(...you said that...) is not a gradual transition,
-
59:11 - 59:14implies there must be a set the conditions under which
-
59:14 - 59:19that shift is being driven, that is unique to humans but it's not found in the great apes, otherwise
-
59:19 - 59:23presumably there would have been the same (...transition...) in terms of (...).
-
59:23 - 59:25Do you have any sorts of thoughts on
-
59:25 - 59:31what might be those conditions that would generate that kind of phase change?]
-
59:32 - 59:36I'm generally sympathetic to some version of Social Brain Hypothesis.
-
59:36 - 59:40Humans are an incredibly social species, they live in very large social groups...
-
59:40 - 59:46That seems to select for a whole lot of forms of social intelligence.
-
59:46 - 59:50Now, the Social Brain Hypothesis/Machiavellian Intelligence Hypothesis,
-
59:50 - 59:52whatever you want to call it,
-
59:52 - 59:54exists in various different forms, and people are still arguing on the nuances,
-
59:54 - 59:57but it does seem to me that there is quite a lot of agreement that
-
59:57 - 60:02the hyper sociality of humans has driven a particular social intelligence,
-
60:02 - 60:06which gives you the meta-psychology that I've been talking about.
-
60:06 - 60:11[Possibly the further development (...that could be made about your argument is to state the...)
-
60:11 - 60:17necessary condition with the argument (...) (...sufficient argument...)
-
60:17 - 60:21in a sense that (... something well-argued would say...)
-
60:21 - 60:25Well, why did we continue in this trajectory towards our present communicative capacities;
-
60:25 - 60:33why didn't we plateau at some (...more novel...) model of communicative ability (…) as well as driving further
-
60:33 - 60:40development of communication abilities (...) and not to be reaching a new plateau (...)
-
60:40 - 60:45something a little bit smarter than the great apes but well below modern humans...]
-
60:45 - 60:50That's why this line here. The real continuity is in social intelligence.
-
60:50 - 60:53And one thing that I say in the book is that,
-
60:53 - 60:58in a way—this isn't strictly true, but in a way—the way to think about human communication
-
60:58 - 61:03is not as a communication system, but as a form of social intelligence/social cognition.
-
61:03 - 61:09I am trying to manipulate your mind right now, you are letting me, and—equally—you're trying
-
61:09 - 61:12to read my mind –we're just helping each other, because we've got the set of tools that
-
61:12 - 61:15allow us to do it in a particularly rich way.
-
61:15 - 61:18So, it's not the case that there is a kind of simple form of communication
-
61:18 - 61:22(...that I stop telling you, that once you get it, you stop there...).
-
61:22 - 61:28This whole communication thing is on the cline of social intelligence,
-
61:28 - 61:30it's at one particular end.
-
61:30 - 61:33[But it did stop in the apes. That is, presumably...]
-
61:33 - 61:36No, no. Because... Oh, sorry yes!
-
61:36 - 61:40[Social intelligence... The argument is also, to whatever extent it was advantageous
-
61:40 - 61:43for our hominid ancestors,
-
61:43 - 61:49presumably is advantageous for our almost identical chimpanzees ancestors
-
61:49 - 61:52close to the divergence of (...Hominoidea...)]
-
61:52 - 61:56Would you buy any version of the Machiavellian Intelligence/Social Brain Hypothesis?
-
61:56 - 62:01[I don't have any objections with the Machiavellian argument as long as
-
62:01 - 62:04one introduces what would be the conditions
-
62:04 - 62:10under which further development of Machiavellian intelligence has a payoff, rather than just
-
62:10 - 62:13presuming that somehow it just naturally develops that way.
-
62:13 - 62:16Because once that you start down that route,
-
62:16 - 62:22you must follow it all the way to human kinds of communication.
-
62:22 - 62:25It seems to me what's missing in the argument is,
-
62:25 - 62:30what are those external conditions that would be driving the continued development of
-
62:30 - 62:36Machiavellian intelligence. Because, certainly, it's hard to imagine (...it as...)
-
62:36 - 62:43a self-generating process that couldn't stop until it got to the level of our human communication.]
-
62:43 - 62:48[But if communication is socially beneficial...?]
-
62:48 - 62:52[But what would be the conditions under which it is socially beneficial for
-
62:52 - 62:56hominid ancestors but not chimpanzee ancestors?
-
62:56 - 63:00That question... I would reframe it as...
-
63:00 - 63:06[The ability of the individual chimpanzees didn't also...
-
63:09 - 63:13... evolve (...) by accident?]
-
63:14 - 63:18[(...mutations...) didn't actually have to occur, you know.]
-
63:19 - 63:26[...unintelligible...]
-
63:26 - 63:30So, the answer in the Social Brain Hypothesis is that humans are more social because
-
63:30 - 63:35we do live in larger groups. We do have, you know, a richer array of interactions...
-
63:35 - 63:38[Why can't it be a happy accident?]
-
63:38 - 63:41[If we look down at the development of human evolution that's true,
-
63:41 - 63:44that's what we've come to at present, yes,
-
63:44 - 63:49we live in larger groups, but certainly initially we weren't. That is, at the time of divergence of
-
63:49 - 63:55our hominid ancestors up in the Serengeti Plain or whatever, the size of the social groups
-
63:55 - 63:59(....follows no difference from...) the size of the chimpanzees social groups.]
-
63:59 - 64:03[So that's the thing that differ. So, you know, specialty in hominids is
-
64:03 - 64:06very very old and predates encephalization,
-
64:06 - 64:09and our specialty is going to favor biparental care.
-
64:09 - 64:12We're the only primate that has extensive biparental care
-
64:12 - 64:19in large groups, so, you know, we can go on all day about things that might have lead to
-
64:19 - 64:24an upper ceiling that isn't there in apes that was there in hominids...]
-
64:24 - 64:28[I don't disagree with (...),
-
64:28 - 64:32...but I just want to bring attention to the fact that, in this kind of arguments,
-
64:32 - 64:36we also need to also be able to identify why was it that
-
64:36 - 64:39our particular lineage was driven in this direction
-
64:39 - 64:45whereas the ape lineage was not. What was different that was going on in our linage?]
-
64:45 - 64:47[But to be honest, that's not Thom...]
-
64:47 - 64:51[ I didn't want to say that, but (...)] (laughs)
-
64:51 - 64:57[He's saying you get human communicative abilities once
-
64:57 - 65:04you reach a threshold of social intelligence. Then the answer is not on him to explain how you reach
-
65:04 - 65:09that threshold, because—as we agreed—there are many things that might have contributed to it]
-
65:09 - 65:14[Well, obviously it might not be on Thom's.. It's up to him to decide whether
-
65:14 - 65:17it is or not (...we're not going to decide...) for him.
-
65:17 - 65:21But the answer is on somebody. Or at least to recognize that this is obviously a critical aspect of
-
65:21 - 65:28the argument in the sense of (...) . At least to recognize that there needs to be some way of
-
65:28 - 65:35accounting for why did occur this linage and it did not in others where the specific kinds of
-
65:35 - 65:42mechanisms one is talking about presumably were also operating (...) social intelligence, presumably
-
65:42 - 65:44was also beneficial in the context of chimpanzees (...)
-
65:44 - 65:47argument about social intelligence development (...)
-
65:47 - 65:52we're looking at changes in primates in terms of social complexity and then response to (...)
-
65:52 - 65:57(...that developing of...) social intelligence. Why does that particular trajectory terminate
-
65:57 - 66:00whereas ours doesn't? I'm not saying that you
-
66:00 - 66:05have to have the answer (...) rather it seems to me that this part of the argument at some point needs
-
66:05 - 66:10to be addressed (...). Of course, we might all come up with just-so stories about what might be
-
66:10 - 66:14the reasons for them (....) carrying the debate as well.]
-
66:15 - 66:17Can I take a different question?
-
66:19 - 66:22[This is a comment, not a question]
-
66:22 - 66:23OK
-
66:23 - 66:28[It's about this issue of the ability of attribute communicative intent to an interlocutor's behavior
-
66:28 - 66:34even when you've never seen or heard that particular behavior before.
-
66:34 - 66:39And I'm sure you know about this –it's an experiment out of Tomasello's group that
-
66:39 - 66:42addresses this directly, where the task is to choose
-
66:42 - 66:48the box that has a reward when the reward's been hidden and there are three boxes, visually different
-
66:48 - 66:52from each other. So, there's two experimenters, one directly facing the subject,
-
66:52 - 66:55the other standing is behind the subject,
-
66:55 - 66:59who communicates something to the subject, maybe a child or an ape,
-
66:59 - 67:02either by pointing at the right box
-
67:02 - 67:06—and that, of course, both the apes and the children have seen lots of pointing—
-
67:06 - 67:09or holding up a little replica of the box or putting on a marker on the box.
-
67:09 - 67:12And those, presumably, the child has never seen before
-
67:12 - 67:16and yet the children are much better at picking the correct box
-
67:16 - 67:20–much better than chance, whereas the apes don't do better than chance.
-
67:20 - 67:24So that's the issue that (...Dan Bornstein...) was debating with you about (...)]
-
67:24 - 67:26Well...
-
67:28 - 67:32So the thing with the object-choice task is... Yeah...
-
67:37 - 67:42So, it's clear that chimps struggle with points in the object-choice task;
-
67:42 - 67:47you can point at one or the other one and they still choose at chance level. It's not clear
-
67:47 - 67:50whether that's a failure to recognize that somebody's communicating
-
67:50 - 67:54in the first place or some sort of...
-
67:56 - 68:01Actually, I don't know what the alternative might look like. I kind of feel
-
68:01 - 68:06like there's an alternative that is some sort of cultural explanation there...
-
68:12 - 68:18I'm not sure what methods (….). It’s certainly the case that the results of the object-choice task
-
68:18 - 68:22is consistent with what I'm saying, so in a way I'm looking for (...)
-
68:23 - 68:29[You see, to me is very convincing. It seems to indicate that a child, even a 3-year-old child, will,
-
68:29 - 68:33whenever the adult is looking at the child or
-
68:33 - 68:36in other way indicating that (...the child should pay attention...),
-
68:36 - 68:40no matter what the adult does—even if is something the kid has never seen before—
-
68:40 - 68:45whatever this is, it's got to be something that is intended to make me understand something.]
-
68:45 - 68:49I certainly think that kids are communicating ostensively and
-
68:49 - 68:53are understanding ostensive communication, which is what you're describing.
-
68:53 - 68:57You won't find me (...arguing against that...). I mean, I'm agreeing that
-
68:57 - 69:03what you're observing is entirely consistent with what I am arguing. I guess (...) a direct test of
-
69:03 - 69:07the 4 things that I wanted to point, that I'm trying to address, and
-
69:07 - 69:13that's why (...I haven't talked about it in the book but...) I do get a passing mentioning.
-
69:19 - 69:28[I'm just wondering... You keep saying you're trying to modify our mental representations, (...) modify yours
-
69:28 - 69:34I'm just wondering, how much of this (...whole dual thing...) is dependent on
-
69:34 - 69:42this picture of communication that heavily emphasizes mental representation.
-
69:42 - 69:46I missed the beginning of your talk so maybe you mentioned something about this,
-
69:46 - 69:54but Wittgenstein once said something about how, you know, tools all serve to modify something,
-
69:54 - 70:02so the chisel modifies the piece of wood and, you know... the hammer modifies the nail...
-
70:02 - 70:08What does it take to modify (...) my idea of the (...length of the thing...)?
-
70:08 - 70:13And then Wittgenstein says, What is accomplished by this assimilation of expressions?
-
70:13 - 70:21So, I'm just wondering, what is done by... What is the consequence of viewing
-
70:21 - 70:26everything in terms of mental representations and intentions?
-
70:26 - 70:36And one reason I'm thinking about this is, you may well be right that social communication and people...
-
70:36 - 70:39That the point of continuity between earlier primates
-
70:39 - 70:43and us is social communication.
-
70:43 - 70:48But there have been a lot of patterns found by conversation analysts that
-
70:48 - 70:57don't emphasize mental representations. They sort of emphasize adjacency pairs, more of a "dance",
-
70:57 - 71:04which may involve keeping track of things and maybe involves keeping track of intentions.
-
71:05 - 71:11And, I guess... (how do you pronounce his name, Federico Rossano?)
-
71:11 - 71:17Rossano has found that in a lot of primates there are
-
71:17 - 71:20sort of similar timings, some similar stuff.
-
71:20 - 71:25So, maybe this (...conversationalist analysts stuff...) is just the
-
71:25 - 71:30(...conventionalized content...) that you're kind of setting to the side,
-
71:30 - 71:33but I'm just wondering –if you focused more
-
71:33 - 71:39on that kind of pattern you come up with slightly different take on things...]
-
71:39 - 71:49I don't see the two... I don't see (...as foxing...) on the conversational patterns and
-
71:49 - 71:51forms of the conventions, and focusing on
-
71:51 - 71:55the mental representation as being in any way (...on a par...) (...).
-
71:55 - 71:58So the former is a consequence of the latter.
-
71:58 - 72:02[Wait, which is a consequence? Just spell it out]
-
72:02 - 72:09We're engaged in the mental manipulation and mind-reading that I was talking about earlier and...
-
72:11 - 72:14[And that leads to the conversational (...)?]
-
72:14 - 72:18That with lead to—well, that and many other things that are involved:
-
72:18 - 72:21the cultural attraction and so on and so forth—would lead to conversational patterns that
-
72:21 - 72:25you do observe in conversational analysis and so on and so forth.
-
72:25 - 72:26I don't see any reason to...
-
72:26 - 72:32[But you said the apes have that patterns and don't have the other stuff, then that doesn't work.]
-
72:32 - 72:38Well, the patterns that we might observe in ape communication and in human communication
-
72:38 - 72:42are not themselves cognitive traits that could be subjected by biological evolution.
-
72:42 - 72:46They're not patterns of...
-
72:46 - 72:48[The ability to produce such patterns!]
-
72:48 - 72:54Sure!... No, no, no! No individual produces patterns; these are patterns of exchange...
-
72:54 - 73:00[Right, (...the ability to...) participate in such patterns. I just wonder if... Again, you seem to be saying that
-
73:00 - 73:06the representations are driving everything, and I'm just wondering if it might be the other way round or
-
73:06 - 73:11if they might be both be driving each other and if it's necessary always to...
-
73:11 - 73:16I'm not one of these anti-representationalist people...
-
73:16 - 73:19but I wonder if it's always necessary or even necessarily helpful.
-
73:19 - 73:24And I just think it might be fun to think of it in a different way just for (...kicks...) (laughs)]
-
73:28 - 73:32I guess there's two points I want to make.
-
73:32 - 73:35Let me draw on the conversation analysis and the patterns.
-
73:35 - 73:40Let me draw on an analogy in a different area of language which I worked on, which is
-
73:40 - 73:42the fact that you we combine things together...
-
73:42 - 73:46They're very basic syntax, is taking things together in various ways.
-
73:46 - 73:52Human language is full of this. And some people have started to uncover
-
73:52 - 73:57simple forms of this, in some non-human primate communication. So there's a
-
73:57 - 74:02natural Darwinian story to (...be told there...). So the last couple of years I've been collaborating with
-
74:02 - 74:04some microbiologists.
-
74:04 - 74:07Cause I've been skeptical, for all the reasons I've highlighted here, that there's actually
-
74:07 - 74:12a continuity there. So I got talking to some microbiologists who work on bacterial communication.
-
74:12 - 74:19And we did an experiment basically replicating the playback experiments done with various monkey species.
-
74:19 - 74:25We found the same results. We found combinatorial communication of the same sort you find in monkeys in bacteria.
-
74:25 - 74:33Now, the point here is that you can see these patterns... This is a system, right?, a communication system,
-
74:33 - 74:38like the patterns (...) is not a trait that is subjected to biological evolution (...) The capacity to engage in patterns,
-
74:38 - 74:43the capacity to combine things together might be. But there's no reason why that isn't very phylogenetically deep
-
74:43 - 74:50I don't see them as cognitively demanding. Bacteria stick symbols together. So do monkeys, so do humans.
-
74:50 - 74:56That's not the thing to explain. And it seems to me quite possible the same thing is true of
-
74:56 - 74:59the patterns that you're pointing to.
-
75:00 - 75:03[Well, maybe true, I don't know]
-
75:05 - 75:14[So... You started out by talking about what is the invention, alluded to, that you might get to]
-
75:14 - 75:16(...) (...patterns of communication...)
-
75:17 - 75:18(...)
-
75:19 - 75:21[Sure, I got that (laughs).
-
75:22 - 75:33The claim, (... further into the taxonomazing game....) people seem to like to talk about what's special
-
75:33 - 75:43for language. And I was wondering what your position was there. Because most of the ingredients that you've given
-
75:43 - 75:48(...where surely...) conventions are not special for language... it all depends on cultural conventions
-
75:48 - 75:50(...that are not linguistic...) ]
-
75:50 - 75:52Yeah, sure.
-
75:52 - 75:58[(...certainly ontogeny is not special for language...). Is there anything, in your view... –for instance,
-
75:58 - 76:05emergent thing that hasn't particularly... There's no linguistic trace that specifically (...have been selected...)?]
-
76:05 - 76:12Right. So, it seems to me that the point number two, the (...join with...) cultural attraction and languages is to explain
-
76:12 - 76:16why we see these the sorts of properties, the structural properties, that we associate with languages. So,
-
76:16 - 76:22people have long observed that languages have various (...differences...) in structural properties,
-
76:22 - 76:26(...independent of...) the relations. And we need to explain why certain, you know,
-
76:26 - 76:29word orders are common while other ones are not.
-
76:29 - 76:34And those explanations..., well, that's where cultural attraction come in, and the sorts of factors of attraction that
-
76:34 - 76:40are going to be important are the ability to stick things together, the ability to engage in patterns, patterns of interactions and
-
76:40 - 76:42so on and so forth. And various other things,
-
76:42 - 76:47which might well be phylogenetic indeed, might well shared with other human behaviors and so on and so forth
-
76:48 - 76:49[ or bacteria (...)]
-
76:49 - 76:54Indeed. Each one is on a case by case basis, but I don't have any one that I want to hold up as, you know,
-
76:54 - 76:58as this one is only working in language. I dont have any reasons to do that...
-
76:58 - 77:02But that's not to say that there isn't one; there might be but I don't know what it is.
-
77:02 - 77:09[So I guess what I'm getting at is—and I confess that don't like when people ask these kinds of questions—
-
77:09 - 77:17what has there been selected for? (...) I mean, natural selection is selecting for a thing...
-
77:19 - 77:23Is any of the things that (...being...) selected for specifically because of (...) ?]
-
77:23 - 77:30Oh, I see . Maybe, maybe not. Once you've got ostensive communication and you've got conventions which are
-
77:30 - 77:37making it more expressively powerful –this is an extremely powerful tool, right? It allows us to do all sorts of things.
-
77:37 - 77:42It seems quite plausible to me that you could have the natural selection for mechanisms that make the acquisition of
-
77:42 - 77:48those conventions and the use of those conventions much more fluent and easy than otherwise might be.
-
77:48 - 77:50If there's such a thing, that is what we should be calling
-
77:50 - 77:53an LAD [Language Acquisition Device] or a UG [Universal Grammar] or whatever.
-
77:53 - 77:57In fact (...I quote you...),you say much the same thing in the book.
-
77:57 - 78:03Whether there is such thing of that sort... I actually dont know. That's why I said maybe maybe
-
78:04 - 78:04[OK]
-
78:08 - 78:15[I will try to keep this really brief because I'll take a lot of your time during the (...rest of your stay...).
-
78:15 - 78:20So, you already know that I disagree with you about a whole "how much do apes do".
-
78:20 - 78:21Yes.
-
78:21 - 78:25But I'd like, to kind of, just bang on about that for a second.]
-
78:25 - 78:26OK
-
78:26 - 78:32[Because I think that the example that you started up with, with—you know: "I'd like a chip please"—none of that
-
78:32 - 78:40would be capture in any of the (...published literature...) about apes, and I think that you're relaying somewhat heavily on,
-
78:40 - 78:50you know, the body of work that manages to get published about primatology, and the meaning of primate signals.
-
78:50 - 78:58And I think that the onus there is really on primatologists to discuss and to really sort of open up our thinking about
-
78:58 - 79:06primate communication. But I'd say that the experiments that are done, and certainly the work that is published about
-
79:06 - 79:12certain communicative repertoires in primate systems, are heavily influenced by, you know, the kind of,
-
79:12 - 79:17"Oh, what makes human language special?! Oh, let's look at primates and the (...) models and (...) models"]
-
79:17 - 79:19Yes, I agree, and I think its a mistake, yes.
-
79:19 - 79:25[But, I'd say that, you know, certainly in ape gesture literature, 80% of the communication gets thrown out
-
79:25 - 79:33because we don't have enough examples of X leads to Y to say anything about it. And so the vast majority of
-
79:33 - 79:43interactions and (...), and you know... Apes spend a huge amount of time, you know, doing this
-
79:43 - 79:45(laughs)
-
79:46 - 79:48None of that is provable,]
-
79:48 - 79:50Sure, I understand.
-
79:50 - 79:54[None of that is objective and replicable... There's a lot of discussion about,
-
79:54 - 80:00Well... is it anecdote...? data...? I don't really know where I fall; I've written things about, you know,
-
80:00 - 80:08[sarcastic tone:] Semantics of the Gesture Repertoire. I'm completely guilty of this, but I think that is very hard to
-
80:08 - 80:14make a claim where you say, "ape communications is this way" and "human communication is this way" when
-
80:14 - 80:22this (...) the published claims about ape communication is being this way are very strongly influenced by exactly the same kind of
-
80:22 - 80:28(...thing that...) sort of faults with linguistics and (...thinking of...) what makes human language special
-
80:28 - 80:30that you criticized in the first half of your talk.]
-
80:31 - 80:34So that's why there are question marks on these (laughs)
-
80:35 - 80:39[I'd preferred it if you'd offered them as series of (...)](laughs)
-
80:41 - 80:45(...)
-
80:45 - 80:49[(...) I wanted to know what you thought in terms of the OI [ostensive inferential] model...
-
80:49 - 80:52Can you have ostension without a code?]
-
80:52 - 80:55Yes, sure. Point... That chip gesture...
-
80:55 - 81:01[No, I know, but I mean do you think could you have the cognitive capacities as a species
-
81:01 - 81:06without having either a very developed natural or conventional code system?]
-
81:11 - 81:17Yes, and you can see it in the natural world. We see it in kids. So ostensive communication
-
81:17 - 81:20precedes linguistic communication in development.
-
81:20 - 81:33[Yeah, no, I agree with you, but I am not sure about this ordering of ...... informational intent and communicative intent
-
81:33 - 81:41as communicative intent follows informative intent. I mean, if informative intent relies to some extent on
-
81:41 - 81:45there being conventional or natural codes. Doesn't it or was I...?]
-
81:45 - 81:46No, I'm not following, sorry
-
81:46 - 81:48[I'll argue about that later]
-
81:48 - 81:49OK
-
81:49 - 81:53[The difference between meaningful and symbolic, right?]
-
81:54 - 81:55I've lost track now (laughs)
-
81:57 - 82:01[The difference between meaningful and symbolic]
-
82:01 - 82:07[We should take this up after (...) because we're now at the end of our discussion.
-
82:07 - 82:10Thank you very much] (applause)
- Title:
- The Evolution of Human Communication and Language
- Description:
-
Thom Scott Phillips
1/5/15
The Evolution of Human Communication and Language
Language is arguably humanity's most distinctive characteristic. What, exactly, is language, and why are we the only species that has it? In this talk, based upon my recent book*, I will argue that the differences between human communication and the communication systems of all other species is probably not a difference of degree, but rather one of kind. Language is a system made possible by mechanisms of metapsychology, and expressively powerful by mechanisms of association. Non-human primate communication is most likely the opposite: made possible by mechanisms of association, and expressively powerful by mechanisms of metapsychology. This conclusion suggests that human communication, and hence language, evolved as a by-product of increased social intelligence. As such, human communication may be best seen, from an evolutionary perspective, as a particularly sophisticated form of social cognition: mutually-assisted mindreading and mental manipulation. - Video Language:
- English
- Duration:
- 01:22:11
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language | ||
Sebastian Wasserzug edited English subtitles for The Evolution of Human Communication and Language |