< Return to Video

Red Herring - Critical Thinking Fallacies | WIRELESS PHILOSOPHY

  • 0:01 - 0:07
    [ Music ]
  • 0:07 - 0:11
    >> Hello. I'm Paul Henne, and I'm a
    philosophy gradate student at Duke University.
  • 0:12 - 0:16
    And in this video, I'm going to introduce
    you to formal and informal fallacies.
  • 0:17 - 0:19
    First, consider the following arguments.
  • 0:20 - 0:24
    Premise one: if someone is allergic to
    peanuts, then she doesn't eat peanut butter.
  • 0:25 - 0:27
    Premise two: Jane doesn't eat peanut butter.
  • 0:28 - 0:31
    Conclusion: therefore Jane
    is allergic to peanuts.
  • 0:31 - 0:33
    Consider this other argument.
  • 0:33 - 0:36
    Premise one: a feather is light.
  • 0:36 - 0:39
    Premise two: what's light cannot be dark.
  • 0:39 - 0:42
    Conclusion: therefore a feather cannot be dark.
  • 0:44 - 0:47
    These arguments probably seemed a
    bit off to you, and you're right.
  • 0:47 - 0:51
    Each argument contains a fallacy,
    though each has a different kind.
  • 0:52 - 0:57
    A fallacy, as we've seen in other wireless
    philosophy videos, is a defect in reasoning.
  • 0:58 - 1:01
    This defect can be unintentional or intentional.
  • 1:01 - 1:05
    That is, I could simply make
    a mistake in my reasoning.
  • 1:05 - 1:09
    Or I could want to trick you into believing
    something by using deceptive reasoning.
  • 1:10 - 1:14
    Either way, it's probably a good
    idea that we are able to understand
  • 1:14 - 1:17
    and identify distinct fallacy types
  • 1:17 - 1:21
    so that we can adequately correct
    any defects in our reasoning.
  • 1:22 - 1:27
    But before we talk about fallacy types,
    let's recall what a valid argument is.
  • 1:28 - 1:29
    Consider this argument.
  • 1:30 - 1:35
    Premise one: if someone is a philosopher,
    then she publishes articles on philosophy.
  • 1:35 - 1:41
    So Tamar Gendler is a philosopher, therefore,
    Tamar Gendler publishes articles in philosophy.
  • 1:42 - 1:43
    This is a valid argument.
  • 1:44 - 1:48
    Actually, although it isn't bearing on this
    argument's validity, Gendler has published
  • 1:48 - 1:50
    over 20 articles, among her other works.
  • 1:51 - 1:57
    This form of argument is called modus ponens,
    and it can be represented as the following.
  • 1:57 - 2:04
    Premise one: if X, then Y. Premise
    two: X. Conclusion: therefore Y.
  • 2:05 - 2:07
    And this is a valid argument form.
  • 2:08 - 2:11
    The conclusion necessarily
    follows from the premises.
  • 2:12 - 2:16
    Remember though, this valid form does
    not mean that the premises are true.
  • 2:17 - 2:21
    It would still be a valid argument if Tamar
    Gendler had decided to become a train conductor,
  • 2:21 - 2:23
    for instance, instead of a philosopher.
  • 2:23 - 2:28
    See the videos on soundness and validity
    if you have questions about this.
  • 2:30 - 2:33
    We can also have an invalid argument form.
  • 2:34 - 2:35
    Let's return to our first argument.
  • 2:36 - 2:42
    This argument, as you might have suspected,
    contains a fallacy, a formal fallacy.
  • 2:42 - 2:48
    And a formal fallacy is exactly what it sounds
    like: a defect in the form of the argument.
  • 2:49 - 2:53
    In other words, there are certain
    forms of arguments that are invalid.
  • 2:55 - 3:00
    This invalid argument form is a formal
    fallacy called affirming the consequent.
  • 3:01 - 3:06
    This fallacy is apparent if you consider
    that Jane just might not like peanut butter.
  • 3:06 - 3:10
    So simply because Jane doesn't like
    peanut butter, she doesn't eat it.
  • 3:11 - 3:16
    Given just the fact that she doesn't eat it and
    the condition in premise one, we cannot conclude
  • 3:16 - 3:18
    that Jane is allergic to peanut butter.
  • 3:19 - 3:22
    This form of fallacy can be
    represented in the following way.
  • 3:23 - 3:32
    If X, then Y. Y, therefore X. And this form
    of fallacy is one that you don't want to use.
  • 3:32 - 3:36
    It's actually one of the fallacies
    frequently tested on the LSAT.
  • 3:36 - 3:40
    So if you're interested and want more
    practice in identifying this fallacy,
  • 3:41 - 3:43
    check out the video on affirming the consequent.
  • 3:44 - 3:49
    We will talk more about this and other
    formal fallacies in upcoming videos.
  • 3:49 - 3:54
    But for now, we need to see that
    formal fallacies are fallacies
  • 3:54 - 3:56
    because of the poor form of the argument.
  • 3:57 - 4:01
    Any argument of these forms will be invalid.
  • 4:02 - 4:05
    So anything can be plugged
    into these bad argument forms
  • 4:06 - 4:07
    and the argument would be invalid.
  • 4:07 - 4:11
    For instance, if meow, then splat.
  • 4:11 - 4:14
    Splat, therefore meow, is invalid.
  • 4:16 - 4:22
    So now that we have a general understanding
    of formal fallacies, what about informal ones?
  • 4:22 - 4:25
    Lt's look at our other example
    from the beginning of this video.
  • 4:27 - 4:32
    Notice that this fallacy arises out of the
    content of the argument, not out of the form.
  • 4:32 - 4:35
    The form may at first glance seem valid.
  • 4:35 - 4:38
    That is if we ignored the
    meaning of the content.
  • 4:39 - 4:44
    Consider that we can use a seemingly similar
    argument form to make a valid argument.
  • 4:45 - 4:48
    For instance, premise one: rain is wet.
  • 4:49 - 4:51
    Premise two: what's wet cannot be dry.
  • 4:52 - 4:55
    Conclusion: therefore rain cannot be dry.
  • 4:55 - 5:01
    And here we have a valid argument that seems
    to have a similar form as the fallacious one,
  • 5:01 - 5:04
    and one that lacks defects in its content.
  • 5:04 - 5:10
    But the content of our fallacious
    argument, given the two meanings of light --
  • 5:11 - 5:15
    lightweight and light color
    -- yields some problems.
  • 5:15 - 5:20
    That is, if we understand the meaning of
    the terms -- the two meanings of light,
  • 5:20 - 5:25
    for instance -- we realize that the argument
    actually has an invalid argument form.
  • 5:26 - 5:29
    Initially, without considering the meaning
    of the content, it looks like the form
  • 5:29 - 5:40
    of the argument is something like, all X are
    Y. What is Y cannot be Z. Therefore no X are Z.
  • 5:41 - 5:46
    But actually, given the shifting
    meaning of light, the form is more like,
  • 5:46 - 5:56
    all X are Y. What is W cannot be Z. Therefore
    no X are Z. This fallacy is called equivocation.
  • 5:57 - 6:00
    And see the video on this if
    you'd like to know more about it.
  • 6:02 - 6:07
    The only way we can understand this defect
    is by examining the content of the argument.
  • 6:08 - 6:11
    If we just looked at the form
    without understanding the content,
  • 6:11 - 6:14
    then we could not detect this fallacy.
  • 6:15 - 6:19
    So as we now know, informal
    fallacies occur because of problems
  • 6:19 - 6:21
    with the content of the arguments.
  • 6:22 - 6:27
    So an argument might have a seemingly
    valid form but commit an informal fallacy
  • 6:27 - 6:29
    because of a defect in its content.
  • 6:30 - 6:32
    Hence, an argument might have true premises
  • 6:32 - 6:37
    and a seemingly valid form,
    yet also commit a fallacy.
  • 6:38 - 6:43
    To reiterate, a formal fallacy means that
    the argument has a defect in its form,
  • 6:43 - 6:47
    while an informal fallacy has a
    defect in the argument's content.
  • 6:48 - 6:50
    Which might also yield a defect in its form.
  • 6:51 - 6:55
    So now that's the difference between
    formal and informal fallacies.
Title:
Red Herring - Critical Thinking Fallacies | WIRELESS PHILOSOPHY
Description:

more » « less
Duration:
06:02

English (United States) subtitles

Revisions