-
[ Music ]
-
>> Hello. I'm Paul Henne, and I'm a
philosophy gradate student at Duke University.
-
And in this video, I'm going to introduce
you to formal and informal fallacies.
-
First, consider the following arguments.
-
Premise one: if someone is allergic to
peanuts, then she doesn't eat peanut butter.
-
Premise two: Jane doesn't eat peanut butter.
-
Conclusion: therefore Jane
is allergic to peanuts.
-
Consider this other argument.
-
Premise one: a feather is light.
-
Premise two: what's light cannot be dark.
-
Conclusion: therefore a feather cannot be dark.
-
These arguments probably seemed a
bit off to you, and you're right.
-
Each argument contains a fallacy,
though each has a different kind.
-
A fallacy, as we've seen in other wireless
philosophy videos, is a defect in reasoning.
-
This defect can be unintentional or intentional.
-
That is, I could simply make
a mistake in my reasoning.
-
Or I could want to trick you into believing
something by using deceptive reasoning.
-
Either way, it's probably a good
idea that we are able to understand
-
and identify distinct fallacy types
-
so that we can adequately correct
any defects in our reasoning.
-
But before we talk about fallacy types,
let's recall what a valid argument is.
-
Consider this argument.
-
Premise one: if someone is a philosopher,
then she publishes articles on philosophy.
-
So Tamar Gendler is a philosopher, therefore,
Tamar Gendler publishes articles in philosophy.
-
This is a valid argument.
-
Actually, although it isn't bearing on this
argument's validity, Gendler has published
-
over 20 articles, among her other works.
-
This form of argument is called modus ponens,
and it can be represented as the following.
-
Premise one: if X, then Y. Premise
two: X. Conclusion: therefore Y.
-
And this is a valid argument form.
-
The conclusion necessarily
follows from the premises.
-
Remember though, this valid form does
not mean that the premises are true.
-
It would still be a valid argument if Tamar
Gendler had decided to become a train conductor,
-
for instance, instead of a philosopher.
-
See the videos on soundness and validity
if you have questions about this.
-
We can also have an invalid argument form.
-
Let's return to our first argument.
-
This argument, as you might have suspected,
contains a fallacy, a formal fallacy.
-
And a formal fallacy is exactly what it sounds
like: a defect in the form of the argument.
-
In other words, there are certain
forms of arguments that are invalid.
-
This invalid argument form is a formal
fallacy called affirming the consequent.
-
This fallacy is apparent if you consider
that Jane just might not like peanut butter.
-
So simply because Jane doesn't like
peanut butter, she doesn't eat it.
-
Given just the fact that she doesn't eat it and
the condition in premise one, we cannot conclude
-
that Jane is allergic to peanut butter.
-
This form of fallacy can be
represented in the following way.
-
If X, then Y. Y, therefore X. And this form
of fallacy is one that you don't want to use.
-
It's actually one of the fallacies
frequently tested on the LSAT.
-
So if you're interested and want more
practice in identifying this fallacy,
-
check out the video on affirming the consequent.
-
We will talk more about this and other
formal fallacies in upcoming videos.
-
But for now, we need to see that
formal fallacies are fallacies
-
because of the poor form of the argument.
-
Any argument of these forms will be invalid.
-
So anything can be plugged
into these bad argument forms
-
and the argument would be invalid.
-
For instance, if meow, then splat.
-
Splat, therefore meow, is invalid.
-
So now that we have a general understanding
of formal fallacies, what about informal ones?
-
Lt's look at our other example
from the beginning of this video.
-
Notice that this fallacy arises out of the
content of the argument, not out of the form.
-
The form may at first glance seem valid.
-
That is if we ignored the
meaning of the content.
-
Consider that we can use a seemingly similar
argument form to make a valid argument.
-
For instance, premise one: rain is wet.
-
Premise two: what's wet cannot be dry.
-
Conclusion: therefore rain cannot be dry.
-
And here we have a valid argument that seems
to have a similar form as the fallacious one,
-
and one that lacks defects in its content.
-
But the content of our fallacious
argument, given the two meanings of light --
-
lightweight and light color
-- yields some problems.
-
That is, if we understand the meaning of
the terms -- the two meanings of light,
-
for instance -- we realize that the argument
actually has an invalid argument form.
-
Initially, without considering the meaning
of the content, it looks like the form
-
of the argument is something like, all X are
Y. What is Y cannot be Z. Therefore no X are Z.
-
But actually, given the shifting
meaning of light, the form is more like,
-
all X are Y. What is W cannot be Z. Therefore
no X are Z. This fallacy is called equivocation.
-
And see the video on this if
you'd like to know more about it.
-
The only way we can understand this defect
is by examining the content of the argument.
-
If we just looked at the form
without understanding the content,
-
then we could not detect this fallacy.
-
So as we now know, informal
fallacies occur because of problems
-
with the content of the arguments.
-
So an argument might have a seemingly
valid form but commit an informal fallacy
-
because of a defect in its content.
-
Hence, an argument might have true premises
-
and a seemingly valid form,
yet also commit a fallacy.
-
To reiterate, a formal fallacy means that
the argument has a defect in its form,
-
while an informal fallacy has a
defect in the argument's content.
-
Which might also yield a defect in its form.
-
So now that's the difference between
formal and informal fallacies.