0:00:00.506,0:00:06.606 [ Music ] 0:00:07.106,0:00:11.166 >> Hello. I'm Paul Henne, and I'm a[br]philosophy gradate student at Duke University. 0:00:11.646,0:00:16.366 And in this video, I'm going to introduce[br]you to formal and informal fallacies. 0:00:16.986,0:00:19.356 First, consider the following arguments. 0:00:19.886,0:00:24.406 Premise one: if someone is allergic to[br]peanuts, then she doesn't eat peanut butter. 0:00:24.856,0:00:27.266 Premise two: Jane doesn't eat peanut butter. 0:00:27.606,0:00:30.526 Conclusion: therefore Jane[br]is allergic to peanuts. 0:00:31.446,0:00:32.596 Consider this other argument. 0:00:33.206,0:00:35.536 Premise one: a feather is light. 0:00:36.146,0:00:38.646 Premise two: what's light cannot be dark. 0:00:39.026,0:00:42.466 Conclusion: therefore a feather cannot be dark. 0:00:43.556,0:00:46.766 These arguments probably seemed a[br]bit off to you, and you're right. 0:00:47.236,0:00:51.116 Each argument contains a fallacy,[br]though each has a different kind. 0:00:51.866,0:00:57.106 A fallacy, as we've seen in other wireless[br]philosophy videos, is a defect in reasoning. 0:00:57.516,0:01:01.076 This defect can be unintentional or intentional. 0:01:01.486,0:01:05.156 That is, I could simply make[br]a mistake in my reasoning. 0:01:05.456,0:01:09.296 Or I could want to trick you into believing[br]something by using deceptive reasoning. 0:01:10.366,0:01:14.276 Either way, it's probably a good[br]idea that we are able to understand 0:01:14.276,0:01:16.856 and identify distinct fallacy types 0:01:17.096,0:01:20.846 so that we can adequately correct[br]any defects in our reasoning. 0:01:22.006,0:01:27.456 But before we talk about fallacy types,[br]let's recall what a valid argument is. 0:01:28.136,0:01:29.206 Consider this argument. 0:01:29.546,0:01:34.706 Premise one: if someone is a philosopher,[br]then she publishes articles on philosophy. 0:01:34.866,0:01:41.026 So Tamar Gendler is a philosopher, therefore,[br]Tamar Gendler publishes articles in philosophy. 0:01:42.136,0:01:43.166 This is a valid argument. 0:01:43.806,0:01:47.936 Actually, although it isn't bearing on this[br]argument's validity, Gendler has published 0:01:47.936,0:01:50.356 over 20 articles, among her other works. 0:01:51.046,0:01:56.636 This form of argument is called modus ponens,[br]and it can be represented as the following. 0:01:57.246,0:02:03.886 Premise one: if X, then Y. Premise[br]two: X. Conclusion: therefore Y. 0:02:04.526,0:02:07.286 And this is a valid argument form. 0:02:07.676,0:02:11.016 The conclusion necessarily[br]follows from the premises. 0:02:11.706,0:02:16.086 Remember though, this valid form does[br]not mean that the premises are true. 0:02:16.586,0:02:21.246 It would still be a valid argument if Tamar[br]Gendler had decided to become a train conductor, 0:02:21.246,0:02:23.006 for instance, instead of a philosopher. 0:02:23.226,0:02:28.386 See the videos on soundness and validity[br]if you have questions about this. 0:02:30.386,0:02:33.016 We can also have an invalid argument form. 0:02:33.586,0:02:35.226 Let's return to our first argument. 0:02:36.246,0:02:41.546 This argument, as you might have suspected,[br]contains a fallacy, a formal fallacy. 0:02:42.036,0:02:48.226 And a formal fallacy is exactly what it sounds[br]like: a defect in the form of the argument. 0:02:49.026,0:02:53.256 In other words, there are certain[br]forms of arguments that are invalid. 0:02:54.836,0:02:59.746 This invalid argument form is a formal[br]fallacy called affirming the consequent. 0:03:00.656,0:03:05.506 This fallacy is apparent if you consider[br]that Jane just might not like peanut butter. 0:03:05.996,0:03:09.826 So simply because Jane doesn't like[br]peanut butter, she doesn't eat it. 0:03:10.536,0:03:15.976 Given just the fact that she doesn't eat it and[br]the condition in premise one, we cannot conclude 0:03:15.976,0:03:17.666 that Jane is allergic to peanut butter. 0:03:18.766,0:03:21.846 This form of fallacy can be[br]represented in the following way. 0:03:22.746,0:03:31.806 If X, then Y. Y, therefore X. And this form[br]of fallacy is one that you don't want to use. 0:03:32.056,0:03:35.666 It's actually one of the fallacies[br]frequently tested on the LSAT. 0:03:36.136,0:03:40.156 So if you're interested and want more[br]practice in identifying this fallacy, 0:03:40.616,0:03:43.036 check out the video on affirming the consequent. 0:03:44.466,0:03:48.726 We will talk more about this and other[br]formal fallacies in upcoming videos. 0:03:48.986,0:03:53.746 But for now, we need to see that[br]formal fallacies are fallacies 0:03:54.126,0:03:56.406 because of the poor form of the argument. 0:03:57.496,0:04:00.746 Any argument of these forms will be invalid. 0:04:01.546,0:04:05.166 So anything can be plugged[br]into these bad argument forms 0:04:05.556,0:04:06.906 and the argument would be invalid. 0:04:07.376,0:04:10.516 For instance, if meow, then splat. 0:04:11.076,0:04:13.936 Splat, therefore meow, is invalid. 0:04:15.626,0:04:21.946 So now that we have a general understanding[br]of formal fallacies, what about informal ones? 0:04:21.946,0:04:25.486 Lt's look at our other example[br]from the beginning of this video. 0:04:26.626,0:04:31.686 Notice that this fallacy arises out of the[br]content of the argument, not out of the form. 0:04:32.156,0:04:35.216 The form may at first glance seem valid. 0:04:35.456,0:04:38.246 That is if we ignored the[br]meaning of the content. 0:04:39.106,0:04:44.486 Consider that we can use a seemingly similar[br]argument form to make a valid argument. 0:04:45.016,0:04:48.106 For instance, premise one: rain is wet. 0:04:48.726,0:04:51.156 Premise two: what's wet cannot be dry. 0:04:51.616,0:04:54.546 Conclusion: therefore rain cannot be dry. 0:04:54.916,0:05:00.636 And here we have a valid argument that seems[br]to have a similar form as the fallacious one, 0:05:01.266,0:05:04.216 and one that lacks defects in its content. 0:05:04.496,0:05:10.426 But the content of our fallacious[br]argument, given the two meanings of light -- 0:05:10.916,0:05:14.976 lightweight and light color[br]-- yields some problems. 0:05:15.166,0:05:19.636 That is, if we understand the meaning of[br]the terms -- the two meanings of light, 0:05:19.636,0:05:24.586 for instance -- we realize that the argument[br]actually has an invalid argument form. 0:05:25.686,0:05:29.446 Initially, without considering the meaning[br]of the content, it looks like the form 0:05:29.446,0:05:40.076 of the argument is something like, all X are[br]Y. What is Y cannot be Z. Therefore no X are Z. 0:05:40.856,0:05:45.636 But actually, given the shifting[br]meaning of light, the form is more like, 0:05:46.316,0:05:56.346 all X are Y. What is W cannot be Z. Therefore[br]no X are Z. This fallacy is called equivocation. 0:05:57.086,0:06:00.126 And see the video on this if[br]you'd like to know more about it. 0:06:01.546,0:06:07.066 The only way we can understand this defect[br]is by examining the content of the argument. 0:06:07.586,0:06:10.896 If we just looked at the form[br]without understanding the content, 0:06:11.296,0:06:13.576 then we could not detect this fallacy. 0:06:14.876,0:06:18.986 So as we now know, informal[br]fallacies occur because of problems 0:06:18.986,0:06:20.956 with the content of the arguments. 0:06:22.126,0:06:27.106 So an argument might have a seemingly[br]valid form but commit an informal fallacy 0:06:27.106,0:06:29.006 because of a defect in its content. 0:06:29.686,0:06:32.086 Hence, an argument might have true premises 0:06:32.086,0:06:36.826 and a seemingly valid form,[br]yet also commit a fallacy. 0:06:38.286,0:06:42.866 To reiterate, a formal fallacy means that[br]the argument has a defect in its form, 0:06:43.396,0:06:47.216 while an informal fallacy has a[br]defect in the argument's content. 0:06:47.536,0:06:50.236 Which might also yield a defect in its form. 0:06:50.806,0:06:54.506 So now that's the difference between[br]formal and informal fallacies.