-
Imagine you and a friend are
strolling through an art exhibit
-
and a striking painting catches your eye.
-
The vibrant red appears to you
as a symbol of love,
-
but your friend is convinced
it's a symbol of war.
-
And where you see stars in a romantic sky,
-
your friend interprets global
warming-inducing pollutants.
-
To settle the debate, you turn to the
internet, where you read
-
that the painting is a replica of
the artist's first-grade art project:
-
Red was her favorite color
and the silver dots are fairies.
-
You now know the exact intentions
that led to the creation of this work.
-
Are you wrong to have enjoyed it
as something the artist didn’t intend?
-
Do you enjoy it less now
that you know the truth?
-
Just how much should
the artist's intention
-
affect your interpretation
of the painting?
-
It's a question that's been tossed around
-
by philosophers and art critics for
decades, with no consensus in sight.
-
In the mid-20th century,
-
literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and
philosopher Monroe Beardsley
-
argued that artistic
intention was irrelevant.
-
They called this the Intentional Fallacy:
-
the belief that valuing an artist's
intentions was misguided.
-
Their argument was twofold:
-
First, the artists we study are
no longer living,
-
never recorded their intentions,
-
or are simply unavailable to answer
questions about their work.
-
Second, even if there were a bounty
of relevant information,
-
Wimsatt and Beardsley believed
-
it would distract us from the
qualities of the work itself.
-
They compared art to a dessert:
-
When you taste a pudding,
-
the chef's intentions don't affect whether
you enjoy its flavor or texture.
-
All that matters, they said,
is that the pudding "works."
-
Of course, what "works" for one person
might not "work" for another.
-
And since different interpretations
appeal to different people,
-
the silver dots in our painting could be
reasonably interpreted as fairies,
-
stars, or pollutants.
-
By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the
artist's interpretation of her own work
-
would just be one among many equally
acceptable possibilities.
-
If you find this problematic,
-
you might be more in line with Steven
Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels,
-
two literary theorists who rejected the
Intentional Fallacy.
-
They argued that an artist's
intended meaning
-
was not just one possible interpretation,
-
but the only possible interpretation.
-
For example, suppose you're
walking along a beach
-
and come across a series of marks in the
sand that spell out a verse of poetry.
-
Knapp and Michaels believed the
poem would lose all meaning
-
if you discovered these marks were not
the work of a human being,
-
but an odd coincidence
produced by the waves.
-
They believed an intentional creator
-
is what makes the poem subject to
understanding at all.
-
Other thinkers advocate for
a middle ground,
-
suggesting that intention is just one
piece in a larger puzzle.
-
Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll
took this stance,
-
arguing that an artist's intentions are
relevant to their audience
-
the same way a speaker's intentions
-
are relevant to the person they’re
engaging in conversation.
-
To understand how intentions function
in conversation,
-
Carroll said to imagine someone holding
a cigarette and asking for a match.
-
You respond by handing them a lighter,
-
gathering that their motivation is to
light their cigarette.
-
The words they used to ask the question
are important,
-
but the intentions behind the question
dictate your understanding and ultimately,
-
your response.
-
So which end of this spectrum
do you lean towards?
-
Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley,
believe that when it comes to art,
-
the proof should be in the pudding?
-
Or do you think that an artist's plans
and motivations for their work
-
affect its meaning?
-
Artistic interpretation is a complex web
-
that will probably never offer
a definitive answer.