< Return to Video

Who decides what art means? - Hayley Levitt

  • 0:13 - 0:16
    Imagine you and a friend are
    strolling through an art exhibit
  • 0:16 - 0:19
    and a striking painting catches your eye.
  • 0:19 - 0:22
    The vibrant red appears to you
    as a symbol of love,
  • 0:22 - 0:25
    but your friend is convinced
    it's a symbol of war.
  • 0:25 - 0:29
    And where you see stars in a romantic sky,
  • 0:29 - 0:34
    your friend interprets global
    warming-inducing pollutants.
  • 0:34 - 0:37
    To settle the debate, you turn to the
    internet, where you read
  • 0:37 - 0:42
    that the painting is a replica of
    the artist's first-grade art project:
  • 0:42 - 0:47
    Red was her favorite color
    and the silver dots are fairies.
  • 0:47 - 0:51
    You now know the exact intentions
    that led to the creation of this work.
  • 0:51 - 0:55
    Are you wrong to have enjoyed it
    as something the artist didn’t intend?
  • 0:55 - 0:59
    Do you enjoy it less now
    that you know the truth?
  • 0:59 - 1:01
    Just how much should
    the artist's intention
  • 1:01 - 1:04
    affect your interpretation
    of the painting?
  • 1:04 - 1:06
    It's a question that's been tossed around
  • 1:06 - 1:12
    by philosophers and art critics for
    decades, with no consensus in sight.
  • 1:12 - 1:13
    In the mid-20th century,
  • 1:13 - 1:18
    literary critic W.K. Wimsatt and
    philosopher Monroe Beardsley
  • 1:18 - 1:21
    argued that artistic
    intention was irrelevant.
  • 1:21 - 1:24
    They called this the Intentional Fallacy:
  • 1:24 - 1:28
    the belief that valuing an artist's
    intentions was misguided.
  • 1:28 - 1:30
    Their argument was twofold:
  • 1:30 - 1:34
    First, the artists we study are
    no longer living,
  • 1:34 - 1:35
    never recorded their intentions,
  • 1:35 - 1:40
    or are simply unavailable to answer
    questions about their work.
  • 1:40 - 1:44
    Second, even if there were a bounty
    of relevant information,
  • 1:44 - 1:46
    Wimsatt and Beardsley believed
  • 1:46 - 1:49
    it would distract us from the
    qualities of the work itself.
  • 1:49 - 1:51
    They compared art to a dessert:
  • 1:51 - 1:53
    When you taste a pudding,
  • 1:53 - 1:57
    the chef's intentions don't affect whether
    you enjoy its flavor or texture.
  • 1:57 - 2:02
    All that matters, they said,
    is that the pudding "works."
  • 2:02 - 2:06
    Of course, what "works" for one person
    might not "work" for another.
  • 2:06 - 2:09
    And since different interpretations
    appeal to different people,
  • 2:09 - 2:13
    the silver dots in our painting could be
    reasonably interpreted as fairies,
  • 2:13 - 2:16
    stars, or pollutants.
  • 2:16 - 2:20
    By Wimsatt and Beardsley's logic, the
    artist's interpretation of her own work
  • 2:20 - 2:25
    would just be one among many equally
    acceptable possibilities.
  • 2:25 - 2:26
    If you find this problematic,
  • 2:26 - 2:30
    you might be more in line with Steven
    Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels,
  • 2:30 - 2:34
    two literary theorists who rejected the
    Intentional Fallacy.
  • 2:34 - 2:36
    They argued that an artist's
    intended meaning
  • 2:36 - 2:39
    was not just one possible interpretation,
  • 2:39 - 2:42
    but the only possible interpretation.
  • 2:42 - 2:44
    For example, suppose you're
    walking along a beach
  • 2:44 - 2:49
    and come across a series of marks in the
    sand that spell out a verse of poetry.
  • 2:49 - 2:52
    Knapp and Michaels believed the
    poem would lose all meaning
  • 2:52 - 2:56
    if you discovered these marks were not
    the work of a human being,
  • 2:56 - 2:58
    but an odd coincidence
    produced by the waves.
  • 2:58 - 3:00
    They believed an intentional creator
  • 3:00 - 3:05
    is what makes the poem subject to
    understanding at all.
  • 3:05 - 3:07
    Other thinkers advocate for
    a middle ground,
  • 3:07 - 3:12
    suggesting that intention is just one
    piece in a larger puzzle.
  • 3:12 - 3:15
    Contemporary philosopher Noel Carroll
    took this stance,
  • 3:15 - 3:19
    arguing that an artist's intentions are
    relevant to their audience
  • 3:19 - 3:21
    the same way a speaker's intentions
  • 3:21 - 3:24
    are relevant to the person they’re
    engaging in conversation.
  • 3:24 - 3:27
    To understand how intentions function
    in conversation,
  • 3:27 - 3:31
    Carroll said to imagine someone holding
    a cigarette and asking for a match.
  • 3:31 - 3:33
    You respond by handing them a lighter,
  • 3:33 - 3:36
    gathering that their motivation is to
    light their cigarette.
  • 3:36 - 3:39
    The words they used to ask the question
    are important,
  • 3:39 - 3:43
    but the intentions behind the question
    dictate your understanding and ultimately,
  • 3:43 - 3:45
    your response.
  • 3:45 - 3:49
    So which end of this spectrum
    do you lean towards?
  • 3:49 - 3:52
    Do you, like Wimsatt and Beardsley,
    believe that when it comes to art,
  • 3:52 - 3:54
    the proof should be in the pudding?
  • 3:54 - 3:58
    Or do you think that an artist's plans
    and motivations for their work
  • 3:58 - 3:59
    affect its meaning?
  • 3:59 - 4:02
    Artistic interpretation is a complex web
  • 4:02 - 4:06
    that will probably never offer
    a definitive answer.
Title:
Who decides what art means? - Hayley Levitt
Speaker:
Hayley Levitt
Description:

View full lesson: https://ed.ted.com/lessons/who-decides-what-art-means-hayley-levitt

There is a question that has been tossed around by philosophers and art critics for decades: how much should an artist's intention affect your interpretation of the work? Do the artist’s plans and motivations affect its meaning? Or is it completely up to the judgment of the viewer? Hayley Levitt explores the complex web of artistic interpretation.

Lesson by Hayley Levitt, directed by Avi Ofer.

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Team:
closed TED
Project:
TED-Ed
Duration:
04:21
Kayla Wolf edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf approved English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf accepted English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Kayla Wolf edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Tara Ahmadinejad edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?
Tara Ahmadinejad edited English subtitles for Who decides what art means?

English subtitles

Revisions Compare revisions