Tamar Gendler: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Politics and Economics
-
0:13 - 0:18My name is Tamar Gendler. I'm professor
of philosophy and cognitive science and chair -
0:18 - 0:22of the philosophy department at Yale University.
-
0:22 - 0:32So philosophy comes from the Greek term meaning
love of wisdom; philo, love; sophos, wisdom -
0:32 - 0:38and every culture from time immemorial has
had a philosophical tradition. There are -
0:38 - 0:45philosophical traditions in western culture
that have their roots in ancient Greece. -
0:45 - 0:51There are philosophical traditions in eastern
culture, great Chinese and Indian philosophical -
0:51 - 0:55traditions. There are philosophical traditions
in Africa. There are philosophical traditions -
0:55 - 1:03in native cultures throughout the world.
What philosophy does in every society of which -
1:03 - 1:10it is a part is asks the question why, why
are things that way they are and should they -
1:10 - 1:15be that way.
The western philosophical tradition to which -
1:15 - 1:22my comments today will be restricted can be
divided into two main segments. On the one -
1:22 - 1:29hand it has a descriptive component, which
asks about how things are and how we know -
1:29 - 1:35that and on the other hand it has a normative
component, a component which asks about how -
1:35 - 1:42things ought to be. So into the first category
fall questions like what is the fundamental -
1:42 - 1:57nature of reality, does God exist, do we have
free will.
Those branches of philosophy are known as -
1:57 - 2:05metaphysics, fundamental questions about what
there is, and epistemology, fundamental questions -
2:05 - 2:11about how we know things. On the other side
of the divide are the questions that I've -
2:11 - 2:18called normative questions, questions about
values and that segment of philosophy has -
2:18 - 2:25three main parts. One of them, aesthetics
is concerned with the question what is beautiful -
2:25 - 2:31and what makes it so. The second part of
that division of philosophy, moral philosophy -
2:31 - 2:39asks the question what is morally right or
good and the third part of that division of -
2:39 - 2:47philosophy, political philosophy asks the
question how should societies be structured -
2:47 - 2:55in order to allow human flourishing and what
makes societal structures legitimate -
2:55 - 3:00Perhaps the most accessible and exciting part
of philosophy for people who have never encountered -
3:00 - 3:08the discipline before is political philosophy,
which asks questions that we as citizens of -
3:08 - 3:15a democracy need to ask ourselves in order
to be responsible participants in our joint -
3:15 - 3:22governance, questions like what is the best
way for society to be structured in order -
3:22 - 3:27to allow people to flourish, questions like
what is the appropriate division of rights -
3:27 - 3:33and responsibilities in a society, questions
like how should the legitimate concerns of -
3:33 - 3:38liberty on the one hand and equality on the
other be balanced and for those of you who -
3:38 - 3:46are interested in studying a subject that
has practical import it may be worth realizing -
3:46 - 3:53that political philosophy brought you the
world as you know it today. Political philosophy -
3:53 - 4:01brought the world Greek democracy. It brought
us the Magna Carta. It brought us the French -
4:01 - 4:06Revolution and the American Revolution.
It brought us communism. It brought us the -
4:06 - 4:13Civil Rights Movement. It brought us feminism
and libertarianism. It even brought us the -
4:13 - 4:21Tea Party. It was, as a result of thinking
about these sorts of questions that these -
4:21 - 4:23movements came into being.
-
4:23 - 4:31So I want you to start by asking yourself
how you would answer these questions. Should -
4:31 - 4:40the State guarantee universal healthcare?
Should there be an inheritance tax? Should -
4:40 - 4:49there be a draft army and should you be allowed
to sell your vote? -
4:49 - 4:54The three people we’ll meet in the lecture
are Thomas Hobbes who wrote a great book called -
4:54 - 5:03Leviathan in 1651, John Rawls who wrote a
book called Theory of Justice in 1971 and -
5:03 - 5:13Robert Nozick who wrote a book called Anarchy,
State and Utopia in 1974. It has been said -
5:13 - 5:21that political philosophy asks two questions,
who should get what and who says so and you -
5:21 - 5:28might think of the three authors that we’re
going to discuss as answering those questions -
5:28 - 5:33in different ways.
Thomas Hobbes is primarily concerned with -
5:33 - 5:40the second question who says so, what makes
the State legitimate and John Rawls and Robert -
5:40 - 5:47Nozick are in a conversation directly with
one another about the question who gets what. -
5:47 - 6:00So Thomas Hobbes lived at the end of the 1500s
and beginning of the 1600s roughly at the -
6:00 - 6:02time of Shakespeare and if you read Hobbes
work in the original you’ll notice that -
6:02 - 6:04the language in which he wrote was somewhat
archaic, but the questions with which he is -
6:04 - 6:12concerned in his great book Leviathan aren’t
questions that just apply to his time, they’re -
6:12 - 6:19questions that concern us today as well. He
asks the question what would the world be -
6:19 - 6:28like if there wasn’t a state and would that
situation be better or worse than the situation -
6:28 - 6:36where there is some form of governance.
In particular, Hobbes famously asks people -
6:36 - 6:41to imagine what life would be like in what
he calls the state of nature, -
6:41 - 6:48a situation in which there is no external
governing body and Hobbes points out that -
6:48 - 6:57in the state of nature people are all roughly
equal in the following relevant way. All -
6:57 - 7:04of us, no matter how physically strong or
intellectually clever are at risk of having -
7:04 - 7:11the work that we do disrupted by others, at
risk of having the property that we’ve acquired -
7:11 - 7:19taken by others, at risk of having the things
that we see as important to our lives destroyed -
7:19 - 7:26by others because all of us sleep and all
of us go away from things that are important -
7:26 - 7:32to us.
As a result says Hobbes, in the state of nature -
7:32 - 7:39people need to expand a tremendous amount
of energy protecting their goods. there -
7:39 - 7:44is no opportunity in the state of nature to
do the sorts of things which human beings -
7:44 - 7:46think makes life valuable, things like develop
relationships to individuals far from us, -
7:46 - 7:46things like Hobbes mentions creating the skills
of navigation, writing poetry, making music -
7:46 - 7:49or any of the things that you find valuable
in your life. All of those things Hobbes -
7:49 - 7:57point out are possible only because you have
a kind of security and safety. By contrast, -
7:57 - 8:07life in the state of nature says Hobbes, is
solitary, poor, nasty, broodish and short. -
8:07 - 8:16The question is how can we get out of the
state of nature? How can we get out of this -
8:16 - 8:25situation of perpetual fear, for as Hobbes
point out active war isn’t what disrupts -
8:25 - 8:33human activity. The fear of war is sufficient
to disrupt human activity. Think of the -
8:33 - 8:41ways in which after 9/11 your anxiety about
your security was raised so that at every -
8:41 - 8:47moment you were attentive to things around
you, hyper vigilant to what risks you might -
8:47 - 8:55face. So Hobbes’ idea in arguing for the
legitimacy of government is to begin by asking -
8:55 - 9:01what would it be like if there were no government
and to point out that that’s a state which -
9:01 - 9:03all of us find undesirable.
There are says Hobbes, three things which -
9:03 - 9:03motivate people to try to leave the state
of nature. They are, to quote directly, -
9:03 - 9:04“fear of death, desire of such things as
are necessary for commodious living and the -
9:04 - 9:05hope by their industry to obtain them”.
-
9:05 - 9:06So the puzzle the Hobbes raises is how can
we get out of the state of nature and in subsequent -
9:06 - 9:13years game theorists who work at the intersection
of what you might think of as philosophy and -
9:13 - 9:21economics have developed a way of representing
the problem which Hobbes thinks we face in -
9:21 - 9:23the state of nature.
-
9:23 - 9:29Life in the state of nature, according to
Hobbes, embodies what is sometimes called -
9:29 - 9:35a prisoner’s dilemma. The prisoner’s
dilemma gets its name from a famous example -
9:35 - 9:41. A small town police officer has captured
two criminals and he wants to entice them -
9:41 - 9:49to confess, so what he does is he creates
a structure of prison sentences where it’s -
9:49 - 9:55advantageous for each of the prisoners to
confess regardless of what the other one does. -
9:55 - 10:00We can illustrate a prisoner’s dilemma by
thinking about the situation of the United -
10:00 - 10:07States and the Soviet Union during the Cold
War. Both sides would have preferred de-escalation -
10:07 - 10:10in terms of armament. Both sides would have
been happy to use the money that they were -
10:10 - 10:17building missiles with to build schools and
highways and hospitals, but both sides also -
10:17 - 10:26realized that if they engaged in unilateral
disarmament they would be at risk. Let’s -
10:26 - 10:32look at the structure that governed the choice
that those two countries faced. -
10:32 - 10:37The United States couldn’t choose whether
the Soviet Union disarmed or not. It could -
10:37 - 10:42only choose whether it disarmed. The Soviet
Union couldn’t choose whether the United -
10:42 - 10:49States disarmed or not. It could only choose
whether it disarmed. For both countries -
10:49 - 10:54their first choice was that the other country
disarmed while they kept their weapons. -
10:54 - 11:35Because of that what was
rational for both countries to do was to keep
their arms. -
11:35 - 11:59What that meant is that
the rational choice for both parties was to
keep their arms rather than ending up in their -
11:59 - 12:06second choice situation, the situation where
I have money to spend on my schools and hospitals -
12:06 - 12:13and Russia has money to spend on its schools
and hospitals both countries in order to be -
12:13 - 12:25rational needed to spend resources on armament.
This structure occurs over and over again -
12:25 - 12:30in human transactions. So unless there is
some sort of enforcement mechanism in place -
12:30 - 12:36we will end up like the US and the Soviet
Union during the arms race, with our third -
12:36 - 12:43choice situation. So the general problem
with which the prisoner’s dilemma confronts -
12:43 - 12:49us is that if we behave in rational ways we
will always end up not cooperating and the -
12:49 - 12:50puzzle that Hobbes’ confronts in his political
philosophy is the question how is it possible -
12:50 - 12:52to bring human beings into their second choice
situation, where they cooperate with one another -
12:52 - 12:56rather than competing.
It turns out that in lots of small local interactions -
12:56 - 13:02human beings do manage to find a way out of
this scenario. Famously, during the First -
13:02 - 13:07World War when soldiers were engaged in trench
warfare the Germans and the Americans developed -
13:07 - 13:14a kind of truce whereby soldiers from one
side could leave their trenches and get some -
13:14 - 13:19fresh air without getting shot and then soldiers
from the other side would leave their trenches -
13:19 - 13:25and get some fresh air without getting shot.
The idea was that as long as the other side -
13:25 - 13:32was behaving peacefully it was rational for
you to behave peacefully as well -
13:32 - 13:40If you fail to cooperate or if it seems to
me that you have failed to cooperate I will -
13:40 - 13:49retaliate by not cooperating. Because of
the possibility that informal modes of cooperation -
13:49 - 13:57can breakdown Hobbes insisted that in order
to get out of the state of nature we need -
13:57 - 14:01not only informal arrangements with one another,
but a body that regulates human interactions. -
14:01 - 14:10Hobbes concludes that it’s in our rational
self interest to submit our will to a sovereign -
14:10 - 14:20whom he calls the Leviathan and thereby to
get ourselves out of the state of nature. -
14:20 - 14:35Let’s fast forward 300 years. A half century
later philosopher John Locke writes another -
14:35 - 14:41book about social contract theory and 50 or
so years after that the philosopher John Jacques -
14:41 - 14:49Rousseau writes a similar work, each of them
refining Hobbes’ notion of the social contract. -
14:49 - 14:56Together these three pictures of what makes
a state legitimate allow the thinkers who -
14:56 - 15:04lie at the heart of the American and French
Revolutions to articulate a picture of human -
15:04 - 15:13rights that makes those revolutions legitimate.
From the French and American Revolutions which -
15:13 - 15:20give voice to the citizens we move through
the 18th century to the emancipation of the -
15:20 - 15:27serfs in Russia and a general democratization
of society, a recognition that individual’s -
15:27 - 15:32votes should not be dependent upon them being
landholders, but should rather be open to -
15:32 - 15:39people of all social classes.
Extending this idea Karl Marx writes the Communist -
15:39 - 15:49Manifesto and an entire enormous nation, Russia
in 1917 reshapes the fundamental structure -
15:49 - 15:57of its society in response to a work of political
philosophy. At the same time the tradition -
15:57 - 16:04which gave rise to the revolutions in the
18th century, one that says all human beings -
16:04 - 16:09have the right to have their voices heard,
gives rise on the one hand to the women’s -
16:09 - 16:15voting movement in England and America and
then to the Civil Rights movement on United -
16:15 - 16:23States’ soil expanding and expanding out
of Hobbes’ fundamental idea that a government -
16:23 - 16:30to be legitimate, must be in response to the
needs of its people. We get during this -
16:30 - 16:38300 year period an incredible opening up of
political rights of a sort unknown in the -
16:38 - 16:49history of civilization.
Political philosopher John Rawls was born -
16:49 - 16:57in the early 20th century in the American
south. He was of a generation where he and -
16:57 - 17:05all his friends went off to serve in the Second
World War and returned from that war concerned -
17:05 - 17:14with how it’s possible to create a stable
and just society. Rawls spent most of his -
17:14 - 17:24academic career thinking about that question
as a professor of philosophy at Harvard University -
17:24 - 17:33and when he was in his early 50s in the middle
of the 1960s and early 1970s as the Vietnam -
17:33 - 17:41War was raging, as social protests were going
on around him, as American society was reshaping -
17:41 - 17:47itself in ways that voice was given to the
needs of the disenfranchised, Rawls tried -
17:47 - 17:56to articulate in the great social contract
tradition a picture of what a just society -
17:56 - 18:01looks like and how a just society should be
structured. -
18:01 - 18:12It’s in this time that John Rawls sets out
to write his work, The Theory of Justice. It’s -
18:12 - 18:19worth listening to the extraordinary opening
words of Rawls’ book. He says, “Justice -
18:19 - 18:28is the first virtue of social institutions
as truth is of systems of thought.” -
18:28 - 18:53Rawls’ fundamental assumption in articulating
what a just society looks like is that each -
18:53 - 19:02person possesses a certain inviolability which
cannot be overridden even if doing so would -
19:02 - 19:11be of greater benefit to the society as a
whole. In so doing he challenges what had -
19:11 - 19:20become a dominant picture of what justice
and morality demand. That picture can be -
19:20 - 19:26traced to the 19th century works of the British
philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart -
19:26 - 19:30Mill and is known and utilitarianism. It’s
an incredibly appealing view. -
19:30 - 19:37What the view says is that an act is morally
right if it produces the greatest good for -
19:37 - 19:44the greatest number of people. If I face
a choice between saving one person and saving -
19:44 - 19:51five where I can save only one group or the
other, utilitarianism gives what many people -
19:51 - 19:57find to be the intuitive answer that I should
save the five, thereby bringing about more -
19:57 - 20:05happiness rather than the one.
The problem with utilitarianism that Rawls -
20:05 - 20:15is concerned with is that it seems that in
farfetched and typical circumstances utilitarianism -
20:15 - 20:23could demand that we violate the rights of
the one to help the many. A famous counter -
20:23 - 20:29example to utilitarianism is that a healthy
man walks into a hospital where there are -
20:29 - 20:35five dying individuals, one in need of a heart,
one in need of a kidney, one in need of a -
20:35 - 20:42liver and two others each in need of parts
that he has. The utilitarian rubric would -
20:42 - 20:50seem to suggest that if those five can be
saved by harming him that that’s what morality -
20:50 - 20:59demands. This picture that each of us has
inviolable rights and that those rights can’t -
20:59 - 21:10be overridden by the needs of others is part
of what is new and exciting in Rawls’ discussion. -
21:10 - 21:17Taking as his premise the idea that justice
is the first virtue of social institutions -
21:17 - 21:27that is that no unjust society is a legitimate
one Rawls asks the following question. How -
21:27 - 21:35should the benefits and burdens of living
together in a community be distributed so -
21:35 - 21:46as to best realize what justice requires?
In particular, he asks what should the fundamental -
21:46 - 21:52institutional structures look like to allow
a society to be a just society. -
21:52 - 21:53Rawls sees himself as the inheritor of the
social contract tradition of which Hobbes -
21:53 - 21:53was the initial voice in the western tradition.
Like Hobbes, Rawls asks what would people -
21:53 - 21:55choose to have their society look like if
they were building it from the ground up. -
21:55 - 22:03Rawls says a just society is one that rational,
free and equal people would choose to contract -
22:03 - 22:12into, but we enter our interactions with one
another will all sorts of inequalities in -
22:12 - 22:18place. Some of us are wealthy. Some of
us are poor. Some of us are endowed with -
22:18 - 22:25certain kinds of intellectual or physical
skills that others lack. If we try to build -
22:25 - 22:32our society taking into consideration those
facts about ourselves we aren’t doing it -
22:32 - 22:40from a position of equality, so Rawls’ insight
is that sometimes the fairest way to make -
22:40 - 22:47a decision is to put yourself in a position
where you have less information. -
22:47 - 22:55Think about what the fairest way to divide
a cake is. The fairest way to divide a cake -
22:55 - 23:04is to ask you to divide it not knowing which
piece you’re going to get. If you divide -
23:04 - 23:12the cake unaware of which part will be yours
you will be inclined to divide it in a fair -
23:12 - 23:24way. This is the veil of ignorance
Let’s go behind the veil of ignorance and -
23:24 - 23:32ask a question that Rawls asks, namely, which
of the two principles that he has derived -
23:32 - 23:39ought to take priority over the other? Do
we care more about fundamental rights or do -
23:39 - 23:46we care about the distribution of income?
So suppose you’re faced with a choice of -
23:46 - 23:53three societies in which you can live not
knowing what role you will play in the society. -
23:53 - 24:04In society number one the average income is
$100,000, but only 85% of the people have -
24:04 - 24:12fundamental rights, only 85% of the people
have the right to vote, liberty of conscience, -
24:12 - 24:18the right to a fair trial. In the second
society the average salary—in the second -
24:18 - 24:25society the average salary is $70,000 and
only 85% of people have fundamental rights. -
24:25 - 24:33In the third society the average salary is
$70,000, but 100% of people have the right -
24:33 - 24:39to vote, freedom of expression, the right
to a fair trial. Which society would you -
24:39 - 24:41choose to live in, average income of %100,000,
85% free, average income of $70,000, 85 % free -
24:41 - 24:45or average income $70,000, 100% free? When
confronted with this choice set anybody who -
24:45 - 24:52is paying attention rejects the second option.
It has all of the disadvantages of the first -
24:52 - 24:58and all of the disadvantages of the third,
but it’s also true that when confronted -
24:58 - 25:05with this choice almost everybody rejects
the first option as well. If you don’t -
25:05 - 25:11know whether you’re going to be one of the
ones with freedom then even though you’re -
25:11 - 25:20guaranteed to have a higher income in the
first society than the third more than 95% -
25:20 - 25:36of people choose to live in the third society.
This idea that when you don’t know where -
25:36 - 25:45you’re going to end up you have an inclination
to be risk adverse is what lies behind Rawls’ -
25:45 - 25:51conclusions about what would be chosen from
behind the veil of ignorance. -
25:51 - 25:52People want to make sure that the bottom is
safe before they worry about what the top -
25:52 - 25:58looks like, so Rawls suggests that to the
extent there are inequalities in a society -
25:58 - 26:04they should satisfy two conditions.
So the first condition is that the benefits -
26:04 - 26:11of those inequalities be accessible to all
and the second and perhaps most controversial -
26:11 - 26:18part of Rawls’ theory is that to the extent
that there are inequalities in a society they -
26:18 - 26:25should be distributed in such a way that they
are to the benefit of the least well off, -
26:25 - 26:33so if it turns out that having a lower tax
rate in the highest bracket produces wealth -
26:33 - 26:42and income in a way that leads those in the
poorest quintile to benefit Rawls says that’s -
26:42 - 26:51okay, but if it turns out that that’s advantageous
only to those in the highest segment of society -
26:51 - 26:59that inequality, says Rawls wouldn’t be
countenanced from behind the veil of ignorance. -
26:59 - 27:05It isn’t a way that people would choose
for a society to be structured if their fundamental -
27:05 - 27:15concern was with justice.
In 2005 two psychologists inspired by the -
27:15 - 27:24work of John Rawls decided to survey several
thousand randomly selected Americans about -
27:24 - 27:30what they thought the distribution of income
would look like in a society of which they -
27:30 - 27:40would want to be a part and they presented
those citizens with two different pie graphs. -
27:40 - 27:45In the one, which you can see on the top the
vast majority of wealth was held by the top -
27:45 - 27:53quintile of society and a small amount by
the second quintile with virtually none held -
27:53 - 28:02by the remainder of the society. In the other
the distribution was more equal. Roughly -
28:02 - 28:09a third of the wealth was held by the top
quintile and the remainder was distributed -
28:09 - 28:21among the remaining four. Given the choice
between those two social structures 92% of -
28:21 - 28:32Americans chose the bottom. As a matter
of fact the top graph, which only 8% of subjects -
28:32 - 28:40chose represents the actual distribution of
wealth in contemporary America, whereas the -
28:40 - 28:44bottom graph represents the actual distribution
of wealth in contemporary Sweden. -
28:44 - 28:48The distribution of wealth where no more than
60% of the wealth is held by the top fifth -
28:48 - 28:52and where at least some of the wealth is held
by the bottom two-fifths seems to be an ideal -
28:52 - 28:53for all Americans, not just for those who
would benefit thereby. -
28:53 - 28:56Rich people and poor people give the same
answer from behind the veil of ignorance. -
28:56 - 29:02Men and women give the same answer from behind
the veil of ignorance. Religious and nonreligious -
29:02 - 29:08people give the same answer from behind the
veil of ignorance and perhaps most strikingly -
29:08 - 29:12democrats and republicans give roughly the
same answer from behind the veil of ignorance. -
29:12 - 29:16As a matter of fact, 85% of the nation’s
wealth is held by the top quintile, roughly -
29:16 - 29:2110% by the second, roughly 5% by the middle
and virtually none of the nation’s wealth -
29:21 - 29:28by 40% of the country.
Does that mean our society is fundamentally -
29:28 - 29:39unjust? John Rawls would give the answer
yes. By contrast Robert Nozick would give -
29:39 - 29:42the answer no. because the structure of society
in which we find ourselves is one that has -
29:42 - 29:44arisen as the result of voluntary interactions,
of human beings engaged in legitimate transactions -
29:44 - 29:46whatever distribution results, says Nozick,
is a just one. -
29:46 - 29:53While John Rawls was writing Theory of Justice
as a distinguished philosopher in his mid -
29:53 - 29:5950s having fought in the Second World War
and then taught philosophy for many decades -
29:59 - 30:06thereafter. Down the hall from him was a
precocious young man in his late 20s who had -
30:06 - 30:15recently started teaching at Harvard. That
young man by the name of Robert Nozick took -
30:15 - 30:24upon himself the task of writing a rebuttal
to Rawls’ Theory of Justice. And three years -
30:24 - 30:35after Theory of Justice was published Nozick
published his retort, Anarchy, State and Utopia. -
30:35 - 30:43Nozick was concerned that Rawls had placed
the wrong fundamental notion at the center -
30:43 - 30:53of his theory.
Nozick writes: “Individuals have rights -
30:53 - 31:01and there are things that no person or group
may do to them without violating those rights. -
31:01 - 31:13The minimal state limited to narrow functions
of protection against force, theft and fraud, -
31:13 - 31:22enforcement of contracts and so on is the
most extensive state that can be justified.” -
31:22 - 31:34Like Rawls, Nozick is challenging the utilitarian
picture. Like Rawls, Nozick thinks the goods -
31:34 - 31:42of one person can’t be traded off the goods
of the community, but unlike Rawls Nozick -
31:42 - 31:51places at the center of his political philosophy
not the notion of equality or justice, but -
31:51 - 31:58rather the notion of liberty.
Let’s look at what a society governed by -
31:58 - 32:07Nozick’s principles might look like. Nozick
famously articulates a view of the conditions -
32:07 - 32:14under which property is legitimately held
and his view is this. It’s legitimate -
32:14 - 32:23for you to own something if you acquired it
in a legitimate way when it was un-owned or -
32:23 - 32:30if you acquired it in a legitimate way from
somebody else who already owned it. If I -
32:30 - 32:38got the property from you as the result of
your having given it to me then no one can -
32:38 - 32:47legitimately take that property away from
me. This may sound relatively uncontroversial, -
32:47 - 32:54but let’s look and see what it implies.
Suppose each of us starts out with the same -
32:54 - 33:05amount of money. Say each of us has $100
and there are thousands and thousands of us -
33:05 - 33:14all of whom are fans of the great 1970s basketball
star Wilt Chamberlain, so suppose you give -
33:14 - 33:2125 cents of your money to Wilt Chamberlain
and I give 25 cents of my money to Wilt Chamberlain -
33:21 - 33:27and our friend gives 25 cents of his money
to Wilt Chamberlain and so on thousands and -
33:27 - 33:32thousands of times until Wilt Chamberlain
comes to have not the $100 with which each -
33:32 - 33:41of us started out, but thousands and thousands
and thousands of dollars. On Nozick’s -
33:41 - 33:50picture any decision to take away any of the
money which Wilt Chamberlain got through this -
33:50 - 33:57voluntary and legitimate transaction is a
violation of rights. Then no distribution -
33:57 - 34:07of income, including one in which 1% of the
people own 99% of the wealth could ever be -
34:07 - 34:17illegitimate because what matters is how it
actually came into being. If all that 99% -
34:17 - 34:26of the wealth came to those individuals as
the result of legal transactions then nothing -
34:26 - 34:33can be done without violating rights to redistribute
it. -
34:33 - 34:41There is no easy answer to this question.
There is a strong intuitive pull to the view -
34:41 - 34:48that Nozick advocates—it is in some sense
theft to take from Wilt Chamberlain what each -
34:48 - 34:57of us has voluntarily given to him. On the
other hand without such theft, more commonly -
34:57 - 35:06known by the term taxation, we will find ourselves
perhaps in the sort of situation that neither -
35:06 - 35:10Rawls nor Nozick wants to be in.
If all of us give our quarters to Wilt Chamberlain -
35:10 - 35:12and his companions.
Instead of having a society of which we’re -
35:12 - 35:23all equally a part Wilt and his wealthy friends
are able to buy access to the media, are able -
35:23 - 35:30to buy advertising time for candidates that
they support, are able to send their children -
35:30 - 35:37to schools where they gain power and advantage
and access to resources with the result that -
35:37 - 35:44the fundamental rights which Nozick as well
as Rawls was concerned with preserving become -
35:44 - 35:51difficult for people to exercise.
The Wilt Chamberlain example illustrates a -
35:51 - 35:56general phenomenon which we face in a society,
one which was foreshadowed in our discussion -
35:56 - 36:03of prisoner’s dilemma. Individual decisions
that are acceptable may be problematic if -
36:03 - 36:12large numbers of people make those decisions.
The problem that this gives rise to is sometimes -
36:12 - 36:21called the Tragedy of the Commons,
so suppose there is a green area where I let -
36:21 - 36:30my cow graze and you let your cow graze and
our neighbor lets his cow graze. So far -
36:30 - 36:36no problem, for each of our cows there is
enough to eat, but suppose that each of us -
36:36 - 36:45instead of having one cow has 50. If you
alone had 50 cows there would be no problem. -
36:45 - 36:52If I alone had 50 cows there would be no problem,
but if hundreds of us have 50 cows the entire -
36:52 - 37:00green space will disappear and all of our
cows will die. This structure manifests -
37:00 - 37:07itself in situation after situation. Over
fishing results from each of us taking what -
37:07 - 37:13would be a fine amount of fish if were the
only ones doing it, but an amount that becomes -
37:13 - 37:21problematic if others are doing likewise.
Each of us polluting a small amount causes -
37:21 - 37:29no problem. All of us polluting together
can lead to drastic consequences. -
37:29 - 37:42Let’s return to our four opening questions
and ask what Rawls and Nozick would say about -
37:42 - 37:49them. —with respect to the question of whether
societies should guarantee universal healthcare -
37:49 - 37:57Rawls would say yes and Nozick would say no.
On Rawls’ picture health is a precondition -
37:57 - 38:05for participation in a civic society and from
behind the veil of ignorance clearly everyone -
38:05 - 38:11would choose a society in which they had the
guarantee of safety on Rawls’ picture. -
38:11 - 38:19By contrast, on Nozick’s this provision
would be possible only as the result of illegitimate -
38:19 - 38:26interference in people’s lives.
With respect to the question of whether an -
38:26 - 38:36inheritance tax is legitimate Rawls would
say yes, Nozick no. Rawls says each of us -
38:36 - 38:46has the right to be born into a roughly equal
community and those who inherit large amounts -
38:46 - 38:52at the moment of birth are disadvantaged in
ways which presumably is not to the benefit -
38:52 - 39:00of the least well off. Nozick by contrast
wonders where Rawls gets the idea that it’s -
39:00 - 39:08anybody’s business to tell me whether I
can give my money to my children. -
39:08 - 39:16With respect to the third question should
the army be constituted by draft or by volunteers -
39:16 - 39:26Rawls would, at least in conditions of wartime,
advocate a draft army.—just as the benefits -
39:26 - 39:33and rights of a society that are fundamental
need to be distributed equally across all -
39:33 - 39:40so to on a Rawls’ picture must the burdens.
The only fair way to distribute those sorts -
39:40 - 39:48of responsibilities is as the result of a
random process. Nozick by contrast would -
39:48 - 39:55be happy with a volunteer army. Individuals
have the right to contract into risk and the -
39:55 - 40:01fact that most of the individuals who contract
into risky situations are those for whom there -
40:01 - 40:08are not so many options isn’t something
that would bother Nozick, though of course -
40:08 - 40:15under both circumstances there are many who
would choose to serve their society—simply -
40:15 - 40:20out of a desire to protect it.
Finally, with respect to the question should -
40:20 - 40:28it be legitimate to sell your vote Rawls gives
the answer no. That is a right that he considers -
40:28 - 40:34unalienable, unalienable because from behind
a veil of ignorance we saw that no one would -
40:34 - 40:40choose to live in a society where such rights
weren’t distributed equally. Nozick by -
40:40 - 40:47contrast thinks that this, like everything
else should be something which is your discretion -
40:47 - 40:54to choose and if you decide that one of the
best ways for you to finance something that -
40:54 - 41:00you care about is by selling your vote to
another person what business is it of anybody -
41:00 - 41:07else to tell you that you can’t.
You, I imagine, have your own answers to those -
41:07 - 41:13four questions. Perhaps they line up completely
with one or the other of the authors that -
41:13 - 41:19we’ve discussed, but what you now have in
addition to your answers to those questions -
41:19 - 42:03are some tools for thinking about why you
give those answers. -
42:03 - 42:08When I graduated from college I spent a couple
of years doing education policy work and then -
42:08 - 42:16decided to go back to graduate school to study
philosophy. In 1990 I was lucky enough to -
42:16 - 42:23enroll as a graduate student at Harvard University
where two of my teachers were the political -
42:23 - 42:30philosopher John Rawls and a man who ended
up being my dissertation director Robert Nozick. -
42:30 - 42:36It’s from the two of them that I learned
what I know about political philosophy. -
42:36 - 42:37What political philosophy and philosophy in
general encourages you to do is to step outside -
42:37 - 42:37the specificity of your own situation. Hobbes
and Rawls and Nozick all recognized that each -
42:37 - 42:37of us wants more rather than less of a share
of the goods of our society, but what they -
42:37 - 42:37ask you to do is to think about how the fact
that you want more rather than less suggests -
42:37 - 42:40that everyone else probably does too.
Philosophy has always been connected to the -
42:40 - 42:46works that are going on in other fields at
its time. In ancient Greece the philosopher -
42:46 - 42:53Aristotle was not only doing work in metaphysics
and epistemology. He was collecting constitutions -
42:53 - 42:59from various other Greek city states to provide
the first catalog of political systems. -
42:59 - 43:04He was doing biological experiments and thinking
about the nature of physics. In the early -
43:04 - 43:04modern period philosophers like Rene Descartes
or Thomas Hobbes were major contributors not -
43:04 - 43:05just to the philosophical work of their time,
but also to the scientific work. Descartes -
43:04 - 43:04did work not just in the domain of political
philosophy, but also work in the sciences. -
43:04 - 43:10This has been true throughout philosophy’s
history that it’s great thinkers think not -
43:05 - 43:04invented coordinate geometry, which we still
know by the name Cartesian geometry and Hobbes -
43:10 - 43:16only about questions central to the discipline,
but also about how those questions relate -
43:16 - 43:18to the fields around them, so philosophers
of mind right now contribute to debates about -
43:18 - 43:19the nature of consciousness thinking both
about what it is for people to be conscious -
43:19 - 43:21and making use of the resources of a 500 year-old
tradition of thinking about the relation between -
43:21 - 43:22mind and body.
People who major in philosophy have gone -
43:22 - 43:27on to do a huge range of things. They go to
law school. They go to business school. -
43:27 - 43:32They go to medical school. Some of them
go onto be philosophers in a professional -
43:32 - 43:38sense, but what philosophers typically go
onto do is to be thoughtful, reflective participants -
43:38 - 43:44in whatever they end up doing whether that
be working in real estate or working as a -
43:44 - 43:49nurse or being a fulltime parent or being
mayor of their town. -
43:49 - 43:55The most profound questions of the world are
the ones which philosophy gives you permission -
43:55 - 44:03to ask and to learn how to answer and it’s
for that reason that the study of philosophy -
44:03 - 44:12can be an enormously illuminating and valuable
part of anyone’s life. Thank you. Thank -
44:12 -you. Thank you.
- Title:
- Tamar Gendler: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Politics and Economics
- Description:
-
Tamar Gendler, Department of Philosophy Chair at Yale University, Cognitive Scientist
Who gets what and who says so? These two questions underlie and inform every social arrangement from the resolution of schoolyard squabbles to the meta-structure of human societies. They are also the basis of political philosophy. Professor Tamar Gendler uses the work of three titans of the discipline, Thomas Hobbes, John Rawls, and Robert Nozick, as a lens to guide us through the taut debate about the role of government in society, asking "Will we embrace the radical state of nature or will we surrender our freedom to the leviathan of the state?"
The Floating University
Originally released September 2011.Additional Lectures:
Michio Kaku: The Universe in a Nutshell
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0NbBjNiw4tkJoel Cohen: An Introduction to Demography (Malthus Miffed: Are People the Problem?)
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=2vr44C_G0-oSteven Pinker: Linguistics as a Window to Understanding the Brain http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Q-B_ONJIEcE
Leon Botstein: Art Now (Aesthetics Across Music, Painting, Architecture, Movies, and More.)
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=j6F-sHhmfrY - Video Language:
- English
- Duration:
- 44:26
![]() |
Amara Bot edited English subtitles for Tamar Gendler: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Politics and Economics | |
![]() |
Amara Bot added a translation |