< Return to Video

Philosophy: Descartes' Cogito Argument

  • 0:00 - 0:06
    (intro music)
  • 0:06 - 0:08
    Hi, I'm Stephan Schmid.
  • 0:08 - 0:11
    I'm teaching at the Humboldt
    University in Berlin in Germany,
  • 0:11 - 0:13
    and today, I want to talk about
  • 0:13 - 0:16
    Descartes's famous cogito argument.
  • 0:16 - 0:18
    Even if you have never heard of the name
  • 0:18 - 0:20
    "cogito argument" before, or of Descartes,
  • 0:20 - 0:23
    you might have encountered
    the argument itself.
  • 0:23 - 0:26
    It is nothing other than the
    famous philosophical insight
  • 0:26 - 0:28
    "I think, therefore, I am,"
  • 0:28 - 0:31
    or in Latin, "cogito ergo sum."
  • 0:32 - 0:34
    This argument has become so popular
  • 0:34 - 0:37
    that it has even become
    the subject of jokes.
  • 0:37 - 0:38
    Consider this one.
  • 0:38 - 0:40
    Descartes walks into a bar.
  • 0:40 - 0:42
    The bartender walks up to him and says,
  • 0:42 - 0:44
    "Hey, would you care for a drink?"
  • 0:44 - 0:48
    Descartes replies, "Hmm, I think not."
  • 0:49 - 0:50
    And poof!
  • 0:50 - 0:52
    He disappears.
  • 0:52 - 0:55
    Now, I admit that this
    joke is probably not
  • 0:55 - 0:57
    the best joke ever, but
    Descartes's cogito argument,
  • 0:57 - 1:01
    to which this joke appeals,
    is definitely pretty cool.
  • 1:01 - 1:04
    The most exciting feature of
    Descartes's cogito argument
  • 1:04 - 1:06
    is not the argument itself, though.
  • 1:06 - 1:07
    It can actually already be found
  • 1:07 - 1:10
    in Aristotle and Saint Augustine.
  • 1:10 - 1:13
    It is rather the philosophical
    question that Descartes
  • 1:13 - 1:14
    tried to answer with it.
  • 1:14 - 1:17
    But who was this guy Descartes, anyway?
  • 1:17 - 1:19
    And what is this question
    that the cogito argument
  • 1:19 - 1:21
    is supposed to answer?
  • 1:21 - 1:25
    Rene Descartes was a French
    philosopher of the seventeenth century.
  • 1:25 - 1:28
    He was dissatisfied with
    the philosophy of his time,
  • 1:28 - 1:31
    which was dominated by
    scholastic philosophy.
  • 1:31 - 1:34
    The scholastics saw to
    answer highly abstract
  • 1:34 - 1:36
    philosophical questions
    mainly on the basis
  • 1:36 - 1:38
    of Aristotle's teaching.
  • 1:38 - 1:41
    Descartes was dissatisfied
    with this kind of philosophy
  • 1:41 - 1:44
    because he considered their
    highly abstract disputes
  • 1:44 - 1:47
    pointless and futile, and
    also unable to accommodate
  • 1:47 - 1:49
    the results of the rising
    mechanistic physics,
  • 1:49 - 1:52
    which sought to account
    for natural phenomena
  • 1:52 - 1:54
    in mathematical terms.
  • 1:54 - 1:57
    On account of his dissatisfaction
    with the philosophy of his day,
  • 1:57 - 1:58
    Descartes came to think
  • 1:58 - 2:01
    that the philosophy was in
    need of a fundamental reboot,
  • 2:01 - 2:03
    a completely fresh start.
  • 2:03 - 2:05
    This is surely a nice idea,
  • 2:05 - 2:07
    but how do you build a
    new philosophical system?
  • 2:07 - 2:10
    Well, maybe it's just in
    a way we usually build
  • 2:10 - 2:13
    new and stable things, such
    as houses and monuments:
  • 2:13 - 2:17
    just by building them up on a
    strong and stable foundation.
  • 2:17 - 2:20
    Yet, what would serve as an
    appropriate firm foundation
  • 2:20 - 2:23
    upon which to build a
    new philosophical theory?
  • 2:23 - 2:26
    Descartes was convinced that
    nothing could do the job
  • 2:26 - 2:28
    better than our most certain beliefs
  • 2:28 - 2:32
    that is, the things that we
    can really be sure are true.
  • 2:32 - 2:34
    Let us now finally turn
    to Descartes's attempt
  • 2:34 - 2:37
    to establish a firm foundation
    for his new philosophy.
  • 2:37 - 2:40
    He carries out his attempt
    most extensively
  • 2:40 - 2:42
    in his "Meditations On First Philosophy."
  • 2:42 - 2:45
    As we said, he wants to
    find absolutely certain
  • 2:45 - 2:48
    and unshakable beliefs that he can build
  • 2:48 - 2:49
    his new philosophy upon.
  • 2:49 - 2:52
    The method that Descartes suggests
  • 2:52 - 2:55
    has become known as
    "Descartes' radical doubt."
  • 2:55 - 2:59
    The main idea is to
    subject all our beliefs
  • 2:59 - 3:01
    to radical doubt, and
    then see which of them
  • 3:01 - 3:04
    can withstand such doubt
    and hence be accepted
  • 3:04 - 3:06
    as absolutely certain.
  • 3:06 - 3:08
    As the application of this method reveals,
  • 3:08 - 3:11
    there is indeed a huge
    difference between the things
  • 3:11 - 3:14
    that we in fact take
    ourselves to be certain about
  • 3:14 - 3:18
    and the things we may justifiably do so.
  • 3:19 - 3:21
    Just consider the following examples.
  • 3:21 - 3:23
    You're doubtlessly pretty certain
  • 3:23 - 3:25
    that you're watching a video right now,
  • 3:25 - 3:28
    or that you have brushed
    your teeth this morning,
  • 3:28 - 3:30
    or that two plus two equals four.
  • 3:30 - 3:35
    Yet are you really justified
    in being so certain?
  • 3:35 - 3:38
    Descartes thinks that after
    having employed his method
  • 3:38 - 3:41
    of radical doubt, you will
    have to admit that you are not.
  • 3:41 - 3:44
    Indeed, there are only very few beliefs
  • 3:44 - 3:47
    that pass Descartes's
    test of radical doubt.
  • 3:47 - 3:49
    Can you be really certain
  • 3:49 - 3:51
    that you are watching a video right now?
  • 3:51 - 3:52
    No, you cannot.
  • 3:52 - 3:56
    After all you could just
    as well be dreaming.
  • 3:56 - 3:58
    The same holds about your beliefs
  • 3:58 - 4:00
    that you brushed your teeth this morning.
  • 4:00 - 4:04
    And most shockingly, perhaps,
    not even mathematical beliefs
  • 4:04 - 4:06
    escape Descartes's radical doubt,
  • 4:06 - 4:09
    for how can we be sure that two plus two
  • 4:09 - 4:10
    equals four, say?
  • 4:10 - 4:13
    True, we have often convinced ourselves
  • 4:13 - 4:15
    that we get a collection of four objects
  • 4:15 - 4:18
    if we unite two collections
    of two objects,
  • 4:18 - 4:21
    but what ensures that we
    did not err every time
  • 4:21 - 4:24
    we convinced ourselves of this?
  • 4:24 - 4:27
    Perhaps there is an evil demon,
    or a wicked neuroscientist,
  • 4:27 - 4:30
    who constantly manipulates our thoughts
  • 4:30 - 4:33
    by systematically distracting
    us when we try to verify
  • 4:33 - 4:35
    our mathematical beliefs.
  • 4:35 - 4:38
    As these considerations show,
  • 4:38 - 4:39
    Descartes's method of radical doubt
  • 4:39 - 4:41
    leaves hardly any belief unaffected.
  • 4:41 - 4:43
    But there is hope.
  • 4:43 - 4:46
    Descartes argues that
    there is at least one thing
  • 4:46 - 4:48
    that we cannot doubt and which we can be
  • 4:48 - 4:49
    absolutely certain about.
  • 4:49 - 4:52
    This is the fact that when we doubt,
  • 4:52 - 4:55
    we cannot doubt that we doubt or think,
  • 4:55 - 4:57
    for doubting is just a form of thinking.
  • 4:58 - 5:00
    But when we can be sure that we think,
  • 5:00 - 5:04
    we can be equally sure that
    we exist while we are thinking,
  • 5:04 - 5:06
    for if indeed we can be
    sure that we are thinking,
  • 5:06 - 5:09
    there has to be something
    that does the thinking,
  • 5:09 - 5:12
    and we are the something, you and I.
  • 5:12 - 5:14
    It is, hence, here that we finally arrive
  • 5:14 - 5:17
    at Descartes' famous cogito argument,
  • 5:17 - 5:19
    "I think, therefore, I am."
  • 5:20 - 5:23
    The cogito argument then
    assures us of the fact
  • 5:23 - 5:25
    that there is at least one thing
  • 5:25 - 5:27
    that is impossible to doubt
  • 5:27 - 5:30
    and is thus absolutely certain.
  • 5:30 - 5:33
    This is the fact that
    we exist while we think.
  • 5:33 - 5:35
    And this is precisely
    the unquestionable fact
  • 5:35 - 5:38
    that can figure as the
    unshakable and firm foundation
  • 5:38 - 5:40
    which Descartes has been looking for
  • 5:40 - 5:43
    in order to build his new
    philosophical system upon.
  • 5:44 - 5:46
    The prospect of building
    a whole world view
  • 5:46 - 5:49
    upon the certainly that
    we exist while we think
  • 5:49 - 5:52
    must strike you as not very promising.
  • 5:52 - 5:54
    Given that we can only
    be certain that we exist
  • 5:54 - 5:57
    while we think, how can
    we ever know, as we seem to,
  • 5:57 - 6:00
    that we live on a planet
    we share with human beings
  • 6:00 - 6:03
    and other animals and
    which orbits the sun.
  • 6:03 - 6:05
    And how can you know that
    two plus two equals four,
  • 6:05 - 6:08
    or that you are watching a video?
  • 6:08 - 6:11
    It is indeed a long road
    for Descartes to restore
  • 6:11 - 6:13
    our certainly in our common sense beliefs,
  • 6:13 - 6:17
    and many of these beliefs have
    to be abandoned along the way.
  • 6:17 - 6:21
    Amongst those are our
    commonly accepted beliefs
  • 6:21 - 6:24
    that materials things are really colored
  • 6:24 - 6:27
    or have other sensory
    properties like tastes,
  • 6:27 - 6:29
    smells, and sounds.
  • 6:29 - 6:32
    It takes Descartes the whole
    rest of his six meditations
  • 6:32 - 6:35
    to walk down this road
    and restore our confidence
  • 6:35 - 6:38
    in our beliefs of mathematical truths
  • 6:38 - 6:40
    and the existence of the outer world.
  • 6:40 - 6:45
    It would take us hours to
    carefully reenact all the steps.
  • 6:45 - 6:47
    However, in order to get a rough grasp
  • 6:47 - 6:50
    of Descartes's procedure,
    it will be worthwhile
  • 6:50 - 6:52
    to reconstruct just one
    step that Descartes takes
  • 6:52 - 6:54
    in order to extend the stock of beliefs
  • 6:54 - 6:58
    that we can justifiably be certain about.
  • 6:58 - 7:00
    The method Descartes employs for extending
  • 7:00 - 7:04
    our certain beliefs
    consists in squeezing out
  • 7:04 - 7:06
    the certainties he has already arrived at.
  • 7:06 - 7:09
    Actually, we have already
    encountered this method,
  • 7:09 - 7:12
    for Descartes's cogito
    argument is such a way
  • 7:12 - 7:16
    of squeezing out a certain
    belief or idea from another.
  • 7:16 - 7:18
    After all, the cogito
    argument is an argument,
  • 7:18 - 7:21
    that is, a transition or an inference
  • 7:21 - 7:23
    from one belief to another.
  • 7:24 - 7:27
    The unshakable belief that
    this argument starts out from
  • 7:27 - 7:30
    is the belief that we are
    thinking when we are doubting,
  • 7:30 - 7:33
    and we arrive at this
    certainty just by observing
  • 7:33 - 7:35
    that whatever we might
    doubt, we cannot doubt
  • 7:35 - 7:38
    that we doubt when we doubt.
  • 7:38 - 7:41
    Now, the cogito argument
    takes this certainty
  • 7:41 - 7:45
    and squeezes out the new
    certainty that we cannot
  • 7:45 - 7:47
    only be sure that we think when we doubt
  • 7:47 - 7:51
    but also that we exist when we think.
  • 7:51 - 7:53
    And it is exactly this
    newly gained certainty
  • 7:53 - 7:56
    of our existence which the
    cogito argument provides us
  • 7:56 - 7:59
    that Descartes squeezes next.
  • 7:59 - 8:02
    In a famous passage of his
    second meditation, he writes,
  • 8:03 - 8:07
    "I am, I exist - that is certain.
  • 8:07 - 8:08
    "But for how long?
  • 8:08 - 8:10
    "For as long as I am thinking.
  • 8:10 - 8:13
    "I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing
  • 8:13 - 8:17
    "that thinks; that is, I
    am a mind, or intelligence
  • 8:17 - 8:19
    "or intellect or reason.
  • 8:19 - 8:22
    "But for all that, I am
    a thing which is real
  • 8:22 - 8:24
    "and which truly exists.
  • 8:24 - 8:26
    "But what kind of a thing?
  • 8:26 - 8:29
    "As I have just said - a thinking thing."
  • 8:29 - 8:33
    As becomes plain here, Descartes
    immediately squeezes out
  • 8:33 - 8:35
    further information about his nature
  • 8:35 - 8:38
    from the certain belief that
    he exists while he thinks.
  • 8:39 - 8:43
    As a result, Descartes cannot
    only know with certainty
  • 8:43 - 8:45
    that he exists, but also
    that he is a thinking thing,
  • 8:45 - 8:47
    a thing capable of thinking.
  • 8:48 - 8:51
    This is still not a lot, though.
  • 8:51 - 8:54
    At this stage, Descartes can
    only be ensured of the fact
  • 8:54 - 8:56
    that he is a thinking thing,
  • 8:56 - 8:59
    and it is still an open question
    whether he also has a body,
  • 8:59 - 9:01
    as we usually suppose.
  • 9:01 - 9:04
    If you are puzzled now, or even afraid
  • 9:04 - 9:06
    that you cannot know whether
    you really have a body,
  • 9:06 - 9:08
    that you really are watching this video,
  • 9:08 - 9:11
    or that you really have brushed
    your teeth this morning,
  • 9:11 - 9:13
    the only comfort I can give you
  • 9:13 - 9:16
    is that Descartes at least
    thought that it can be proved
  • 9:16 - 9:18
    that we can be certain that we have a body
  • 9:18 - 9:21
    and that our senses, by
    and large, assure us
  • 9:21 - 9:24
    of the existence of other
    corporeal things, even
  • 9:24 - 9:28
    though they systematically
    deceive us about their nature.
  • 9:28 - 9:31
    And this can be proved by further
    squeezing out our clear
  • 9:31 - 9:34
    and distinct idea of
    ourselves as a thinking thing.
  • 9:35 - 9:38
    If this promise is not
    enough to give you comfort,
  • 9:38 - 9:41
    then there is only one
    last advice I can give you.
  • 9:41 - 9:43
    Go and get a copy of Descartes's
  • 9:43 - 9:45
    "Meditations On First Philosophy,"
  • 9:45 - 9:47
    and start reading his third meditation.
Title:
Philosophy: Descartes' Cogito Argument
Description:

more » « less
Video Language:
English, British
Duration:
09:58

English subtitles

Revisions