-
(intro music)
-
Hi, I'm Stephan Schmid.
-
I'm teaching at the Humboldt
University in Berlin in Germany,
-
and today, I want to talk about
-
Descartes's famous cogito argument.
-
Even if you have never heard of the name
-
"cogito argument" before, or of Descartes,
-
you might have encountered
the argument itself.
-
It is nothing other than the
famous philosophical insight
-
"I think, therefore, I am,"
-
or in Latin, "cogito ergo sum."
-
This argument has become so popular
-
that it has even become
the subject of jokes.
-
Consider this one.
-
Descartes walks into a bar.
-
The bartender walks up to him and says,
-
"Hey, would you care for a drink?"
-
Descartes replies, "Hmm, I think not."
-
And poof!
-
He disappears.
-
Now, I admit that this
joke is probably not
-
the best joke ever, but
Descartes's cogito argument,
-
to which this joke appeals,
is definitely pretty cool.
-
The most exciting feature of
Descartes's cogito argument
-
is not the argument itself, though.
-
It can actually already be found
-
in Aristotle and Saint Augustine.
-
It is rather the philosophical
question that Descartes
-
tried to answer with it.
-
But who was this guy Descartes, anyway?
-
And what is this question
that the cogito argument
-
is supposed to answer?
-
Rene Descartes was a French
philosopher of the seventeenth century.
-
He was dissatisfied with
the philosophy of his time,
-
which was dominated by
scholastic philosophy.
-
The scholastics saw to
answer highly abstract
-
philosophical questions
mainly on the basis
-
of Aristotle's teaching.
-
Descartes was dissatisfied
with this kind of philosophy
-
because he considered their
highly abstract disputes
-
pointless and futile, and
also unable to accommodate
-
the results of the rising
mechanistic physics,
-
which sought to account
for natural phenomena
-
in mathematical terms.
-
On account of his dissatisfaction
with the philosophy of his day,
-
Descartes came to think
-
that the philosophy was in
need of a fundamental reboot,
-
a completely fresh start.
-
This is surely a nice idea,
-
but how do you build a
new philosophical system?
-
Well, maybe it's just in
a way we usually build
-
new and stable things, such
as houses and monuments:
-
just by building them up on a
strong and stable foundation.
-
Yet, what would serve as an
appropriate firm foundation
-
upon which to build a
new philosophical theory?
-
Descartes was convinced that
nothing could do the job
-
better than our most certain beliefs
-
that is, the things that we
can really be sure are true.
-
Let us now finally turn
to Descartes's attempt
-
to establish a firm foundation
for his new philosophy.
-
He carries out his attempt
most extensively
-
in his "Meditations On First Philosophy."
-
As we said, he wants to
find absolutely certain
-
and unshakable beliefs that he can build
-
his new philosophy upon.
-
The method that Descartes suggests
-
has become known as
"Descartes' radical doubt."
-
The main idea is to
subject all our beliefs
-
to radical doubt, and
then see which of them
-
can withstand such doubt
and hence be accepted
-
as absolutely certain.
-
As the application of this method reveals,
-
there is indeed a huge
difference between the things
-
that we in fact take
ourselves to be certain about
-
and the things we may justifiably do so.
-
Just consider the following examples.
-
You're doubtlessly pretty certain
-
that you're watching a video right now,
-
or that you have brushed
your teeth this morning,
-
or that two plus two equals four.
-
Yet are you really justified
in being so certain?
-
Descartes thinks that after
having employed his method
-
of radical doubt, you will
have to admit that you are not.
-
Indeed, there are only very few beliefs
-
that pass Descartes's
test of radical doubt.
-
Can you be really certain
-
that you are watching a video right now?
-
No, you cannot.
-
After all you could just
as well be dreaming.
-
The same holds about your beliefs
-
that you brushed your teeth this morning.
-
And most shockingly, perhaps,
not even mathematical beliefs
-
escape Descartes's radical doubt,
-
for how can we be sure that two plus two
-
equals four, say?
-
True, we have often convinced ourselves
-
that we get a collection of four objects
-
if we unite two collections
of two objects,
-
but what ensures that we
did not err every time
-
we convinced ourselves of this?
-
Perhaps there is an evil demon,
or a wicked neuroscientist,
-
who constantly manipulates our thoughts
-
by systematically distracting
us when we try to verify
-
our mathematical beliefs.
-
As these considerations show,
-
Descartes's method of radical doubt
-
leaves hardly any belief unaffected.
-
But there is hope.
-
Descartes argues that
there is at least one thing
-
that we cannot doubt and which we can be
-
absolutely certain about.
-
This is the fact that when we doubt,
-
we cannot doubt that we doubt or think,
-
for doubting is just a form of thinking.
-
But when we can be sure that we think,
-
we can be equally sure that
we exist while we are thinking,
-
for if indeed we can be
sure that we are thinking,
-
there has to be something
that does the thinking,
-
and we are the something, you and I.
-
It is, hence, here that we finally arrive
-
at Descartes' famous cogito argument,
-
"I think, therefore, I am."
-
The cogito argument then
assures us of the fact
-
that there is at least one thing
-
that is impossible to doubt
-
and is thus absolutely certain.
-
This is the fact that
we exist while we think.
-
And this is precisely
the unquestionable fact
-
that can figure as the
unshakable and firm foundation
-
which Descartes has been looking for
-
in order to build his new
philosophical system upon.
-
The prospect of building
a whole world view
-
upon the certainly that
we exist while we think
-
must strike you as not very promising.
-
Given that we can only
be certain that we exist
-
while we think, how can
we ever know, as we seem to,
-
that we live on a planet
we share with human beings
-
and other animals and
which orbits the sun.
-
And how can you know that
two plus two equals four,
-
or that you are watching a video?
-
It is indeed a long road
for Descartes to restore
-
our certainly in our common sense beliefs,
-
and many of these beliefs have
to be abandoned along the way.
-
Amongst those are our
commonly accepted beliefs
-
that materials things are really colored
-
or have other sensory
properties like tastes,
-
smells, and sounds.
-
It takes Descartes the whole
rest of his six meditations
-
to walk down this road
and restore our confidence
-
in our beliefs of mathematical truths
-
and the existence of the outer world.
-
It would take us hours to
carefully reenact all the steps.
-
However, in order to get a rough grasp
-
of Descartes's procedure,
it will be worthwhile
-
to reconstruct just one
step that Descartes takes
-
in order to extend the stock of beliefs
-
that we can justifiably be certain about.
-
The method Descartes employs for extending
-
our certain beliefs
consists in squeezing out
-
the certainties he has already arrived at.
-
Actually, we have already
encountered this method,
-
for Descartes's cogito
argument is such a way
-
of squeezing out a certain
belief or idea from another.
-
After all, the cogito
argument is an argument,
-
that is, a transition or an inference
-
from one belief to another.
-
The unshakable belief that
this argument starts out from
-
is the belief that we are
thinking when we are doubting,
-
and we arrive at this
certainty just by observing
-
that whatever we might
doubt, we cannot doubt
-
that we doubt when we doubt.
-
Now, the cogito argument
takes this certainty
-
and squeezes out the new
certainty that we cannot
-
only be sure that we think when we doubt
-
but also that we exist when we think.
-
And it is exactly this
newly gained certainty
-
of our existence which the
cogito argument provides us
-
that Descartes squeezes next.
-
In a famous passage of his
second meditation, he writes,
-
"I am, I exist - that is certain.
-
"But for how long?
-
"For as long as I am thinking.
-
"I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing
-
"that thinks; that is, I
am a mind, or intelligence
-
"or intellect or reason.
-
"But for all that, I am
a thing which is real
-
"and which truly exists.
-
"But what kind of a thing?
-
"As I have just said - a thinking thing."
-
As becomes plain here, Descartes
immediately squeezes out
-
further information about his nature
-
from the certain belief that
he exists while he thinks.
-
As a result, Descartes cannot
only know with certainty
-
that he exists, but also
that he is a thinking thing,
-
a thing capable of thinking.
-
This is still not a lot, though.
-
At this stage, Descartes can
only be ensured of the fact
-
that he is a thinking thing,
-
and it is still an open question
whether he also has a body,
-
as we usually suppose.
-
If you are puzzled now, or even afraid
-
that you cannot know whether
you really have a body,
-
that you really are watching this video,
-
or that you really have brushed
your teeth this morning,
-
the only comfort I can give you
-
is that Descartes at least
thought that it can be proved
-
that we can be certain that we have a body
-
and that our senses, by
and large, assure us
-
of the existence of other
corporeal things, even
-
though they systematically
deceive us about their nature.
-
And this can be proved by further
squeezing out our clear
-
and distinct idea of
ourselves as a thinking thing.
-
If this promise is not
enough to give you comfort,
-
then there is only one
last advice I can give you.
-
Go and get a copy of Descartes's
-
"Meditations On First Philosophy,"
-
and start reading his third meditation.