Return to Video

Free will and neuroscience | Krystèle Appourchaux | TEDxMaussanelesAlpilles

  • 0:06 - 0:09
    So, the title of my presentation is:
    "Free will and neuroscience".
  • 0:11 - 0:13
    I will start, as would
    a good philosopher,
  • 0:13 - 0:15
    by defining the terms,
  • 0:15 - 0:19
    as if I were going to write an essay,
    but that won't be the case, don't worry.
  • 0:19 - 0:24
    Free will is the capacity
    to choose freely,
  • 0:24 - 0:28
    the capacity we have
    to determine our own will.
  • 0:28 - 0:33
    It is a notion first introduced
    by Saint Augustine of Hippo
  • 0:33 - 0:36
    in the 4th century A.D.
  • 0:37 - 0:41
    Originally, it was meant
    to justify the existence of evil,
  • 0:41 - 0:43
    in that, for Saint Augustine,
  • 0:43 - 0:45
    it was not possible that God desired evil,
  • 0:45 - 0:48
    though evil exists, it's a fact.
  • 0:48 - 0:52
    So, it's man that is responsible for evil,
  • 0:52 - 0:56
    and so, man must be free
    in his actions and choices.
  • 0:57 - 1:00
    Today, the advancements of neuroscience -
  • 1:00 - 1:04
    so, neuroscience is all those sciences
  • 1:04 - 1:07
    that study the brain, the nervous system,
  • 1:07 - 1:12
    bringing together anatomy, physiology,
  • 1:12 - 1:16
    as well as psychology,
    informatics and mathematics.
  • 1:16 - 1:21
    So, all these different disciplines
    came together in the sixties and seventies
  • 1:21 - 1:24
    and pooled their data and methodologies
  • 1:24 - 1:26
    in order to study the brain.
  • 1:27 - 1:29
    What we find is that
    neuroscience tell us today
  • 1:29 - 1:31
    that we don't have a free will.
  • 1:32 - 1:36
    I'd like, in the next few minutes,
    to examine with you
  • 1:36 - 1:41
    whether the data are, in fact, alarming,
  • 1:41 - 1:42
    and whether it's not the case
  • 1:42 - 1:45
    that we actually don't have
    any capacity to choose freely,
  • 1:45 - 1:47
    or if there's still a little hope for us,
  • 1:47 - 1:51
    and we do, perhaps, have this capacity,
  • 1:51 - 1:53
    and, if so, to what extent.
  • 1:54 - 1:56
    You could object:
  • 1:56 - 1:58
    "OK, but it's nothing new,
  • 1:58 - 2:03
    science has been telling us
    ever since the 18th century
  • 2:03 - 2:05
    that cause-and-effect
    is a universal law,
  • 2:05 - 2:09
    and when I know what happened
    at any given moment,
  • 2:09 - 2:11
    I can predict what will happen tomorrow,
  • 2:11 - 2:15
    or I can infer what happened in the past."
  • 2:16 - 2:21
    This was indeed the idea Laplace had
    at the beginning of the 19th century,
  • 2:21 - 2:24
    who formulated this idea,
  • 2:24 - 2:29
    by saying for that a supreme intelligence,
    an omniscient intelligence,
  • 2:29 - 2:36
    that at any given moment
    knew every force driving nature
  • 2:36 - 2:39
    and the respective positions
    of everything that composed it,
  • 2:39 - 2:42
    with, furthermore,
    a sufficiently vast intelligence
  • 2:42 - 2:44
    to analyse all this data,
  • 2:44 - 2:46
    embracing in the same formula
  • 2:46 - 2:49
    the movements of the largest
    bodies of the universe
  • 2:49 - 2:50
    and those of the lightest atom,
  • 2:50 - 2:53
    nothing would be uncertain to it,
  • 2:53 - 2:56
    and the future, and likewise the past,
    would be visible to its eyes.
  • 2:56 - 3:01
    So, this is the idea that was
    fundamental to classical physics,
  • 3:01 - 3:04
    which is still used today,
  • 3:04 - 3:10
    since scientists try to ascertain
    regularities, "the laws of nature".
  • 3:10 - 3:13
    Well, man is part of nature.
  • 3:13 - 3:18
    So, do we equally obey
    nature's regularities, it's "laws",
  • 3:18 - 3:21
    or do we reside outside this universe?
  • 3:23 - 3:29
    If we adopt a materialistic point of view,
    which, today, is the most common one,
  • 3:29 - 3:31
    man is part of nature,
  • 3:31 - 3:36
    and it should be possible to explain
    his behaviour, his choices, his actions,
  • 3:36 - 3:38
    in a deterministic way.
  • 3:39 - 3:45
    But neuroscience yields further data
    to be added to this fundamental position,
  • 3:45 - 3:50
    since the experiments
    of Benjamin Libet in the eighties -
  • 3:50 - 3:53
    if I can bring it up ... there we are -
  • 3:53 - 3:57
    the experiments of
    Benjamin Libet in the eighties,
  • 3:57 - 4:04
    showed that an electric potential
    is produced in our brain,
  • 4:04 - 4:05
    a few hundred milliseconds
  • 4:05 - 4:08
    before we are conscient
    of our decision to act.
  • 4:09 - 4:11
    So, how did he show that?
  • 4:11 - 4:12
    He asked some participants
  • 4:12 - 4:17
    whose heads were wired up
    for an electroencephalogram,
  • 4:17 - 4:24
    with an electromyogram recording
    muscular activity in their hands -
  • 4:25 - 4:28
    already we're made to feel
    really free, don't you think -
  • 4:30 - 4:33
    he asked them to look at this dial
  • 4:33 - 4:38
    and to just let come a spontaneous desire
    to raise their index finger.
  • 4:38 - 4:39
    Simply that.
  • 4:39 - 4:42
    And, to him, this was ...
  • 4:44 - 4:48
    the ultimate representation
    of our free will.
  • 4:49 - 4:51
    Well, that's debatable.
  • 4:52 - 4:55
    But, anyway, while the subject
    stared at the dial
  • 4:55 - 4:58
    and let the desire to flex
    their index finger just come to them
  • 4:58 - 5:03
    without determining beforehand
    the moment they would to do it,
  • 5:03 - 5:05
    but, nonetheless, letting known
  • 5:05 - 5:11
    where the luminous dot on the dial was
    when they made the decision -
  • 5:11 - 5:13
    all quite complicated -
  • 5:14 - 5:18
    he asked them to indicate
    the moment they made their decision,
  • 5:18 - 5:21
    while all the while
    their cerebral activity was recorded.
  • 5:21 - 5:25
    They showed, Benjamin Libet and his team,
  • 5:25 - 5:29
    that an electric potential
    is produced in their brain
  • 5:29 - 5:34
    500 milliseconds before the action,
  • 5:34 - 5:41
    and 300 milliseconds before the subject's
    conscient decision to raise the finger.
  • 5:42 - 5:43
    This tends to indicate
  • 5:43 - 5:47
    that our brain, in some way,
    initiates, triggers the action,
  • 5:47 - 5:51
    even before we are conscient
    of wanting to raise our finger.
  • 5:51 - 5:56
    This, therefore, in effect,
    puts into question
  • 5:56 - 5:59
    the tenet of free will,
  • 5:59 - 6:04
    according to which, we are the ultimate
    source of our acts, of our choices.
  • 6:04 - 6:08
    There's no ultimate source,
    since everything is predetermined
  • 6:08 - 6:12
    by cerebral, unconscious events
  • 6:12 - 6:15
    that are completely
    outside our conscious mind.
  • 6:15 - 6:18
    Perhaps I can go on to the next slide.
  • 6:18 - 6:19
    Yes.
  • 6:19 - 6:20
    Or this one, in fact.
  • 6:22 - 6:24
    This just shows the timescale of events.
  • 6:24 - 6:29
    So there, you see the electric
    potential in the brain,
  • 6:30 - 6:31
    so, inconscient,
  • 6:31 - 6:33
    there, the conscious decision,
  • 6:33 - 6:35
    and here the motor action.
  • 6:36 - 6:39
    So, this is the order
    in which events take place.
  • 6:40 - 6:43
    I've tried, in my book,
  • 6:43 - 6:46
    "Un nouveau libre arbitre"
    ["A new free will"],
  • 6:46 - 6:48
    to include this data,
  • 6:48 - 6:50
    to take it into account,
  • 6:50 - 6:54
    and to consider whether these experiments
    could, nonetheless, leave room
  • 6:54 - 6:58
    for a certain capacity of free will.
  • 6:59 - 7:04
    The redefinition I propose
    revolves around two points.
  • 7:05 - 7:08
    Firstly, let's say,
  • 7:08 - 7:13
    it has been proved that certain
    unconscious processes
  • 7:13 - 7:17
    can still be the subject
    of the conscious mind.
  • 7:18 - 7:19
    I'll start again:
  • 7:19 - 7:23
    famous psychological experiments showed
  • 7:23 - 7:26
    that when we make a choice, a decision,
  • 7:26 - 7:28
    most of the time,
  • 7:28 - 7:31
    we are not conscious of the causes
    determining our choice.
  • 7:31 - 7:33
    For example, a Swedish team
    demonstrated that
  • 7:33 - 7:38
    when we ask a participant shown two faces
    to choose the one they prefer,
  • 7:38 - 7:43
    and we magically show them
    the picture they didn't choose,
  • 7:43 - 7:47
    but we ask them: "Why did you
    choose this picture?" -
  • 7:48 - 7:51
    it's totally mean -
  • 7:51 - 7:56
    effectively, the person will rationalize
    that choice that they didn't make.
  • 7:56 - 8:02
    They will say, "That person
    had a nicer smile" etc, etc.
  • 8:02 - 8:08
    Furthermore, this protocol has been
    reproduced in the form of an interview
  • 8:08 - 8:12
    where the participant is induced
    to maintain their attention
  • 8:12 - 8:18
    on the cognitive processes
    that brought them to a particular choice.
  • 8:19 - 8:24
    In other words, when we ask them
    why they chose a particular face,
  • 8:24 - 8:30
    most often, the most probable reasons
    are automatically arrived at.
  • 8:30 - 8:32
    They don't take the time
  • 8:32 - 8:37
    to go back to the moment
    they chose the image
  • 8:37 - 8:41
    and what precisely, conclusively,
    led to their choice,
  • 8:41 - 8:42
    what they saw and felt,
  • 8:42 - 8:47
    what they felt emotionally
    in relation to the face, for example.
  • 8:47 - 8:50
    This interview technique allows us
  • 8:50 - 8:53
    to look at the results of the Swedish
    team in an opposite way.
  • 8:53 - 8:57
    When the participants
    are approached in this way,
  • 8:57 - 9:00
    they detect the manipulation
    in 80% of cases,
  • 9:00 - 9:04
    while before, they were
    manipulated without realizing it
  • 9:04 - 9:08
    and they rationalized a choice
    they didn't make in 80% of cases.
  • 9:09 - 9:15
    So, what this says is that extending
    our own consciousness is possible.
  • 9:16 - 9:19
    Inconscient processes
    can become conscient
  • 9:19 - 9:21
    by redirecting our attention.
  • 9:21 - 9:25
    And this is one part of the definition
    I want to put to you today:
  • 9:25 - 9:29
    that free will is not the capacity
  • 9:29 - 9:32
    to be the ultimate source of our acts.
  • 9:32 - 9:36
    There are, of course, lots of things
    that determine us,
  • 9:36 - 9:40
    but we can, to a certain extent,
    develop this capacity,
  • 9:40 - 9:41
    so it's a learning process,
  • 9:41 - 9:44
    not something we can presume
    to have by nature,
  • 9:45 - 9:49
    rather a training
    of our attentional skills.
  • 9:50 - 9:53
    And the other part of my redefinition -
  • 9:56 - 9:58
    if I can go on to the next slide -
  • 9:58 - 10:03
    There are also neuroscience experiments
    concerning the Stroop effect.
  • 10:03 - 10:07
    The Stroop effect,
    very well known in psychology,
  • 10:07 - 10:10
    is the effect that we have,
  • 10:10 - 10:14
    whereby if I ask you
    the colour of this word,
  • 10:14 - 10:16
    it's easier and quicker for you to answer
  • 10:16 - 10:20
    than if I ask you the colour
    of the word down here -
  • 10:20 - 10:22
    even more so if you are English speakers,
  • 10:22 - 10:24
    since the words are in English -
  • 10:24 - 10:26
    simply because at the top,
  • 10:26 - 10:29
    the colour of the ink
    matches that given by the word,
  • 10:29 - 10:30
    while at the bottom,
  • 10:30 - 10:34
    the colour of the ink does not
    match that given by the word
  • 10:34 - 10:36
    This effect is highly automatic,
  • 10:36 - 10:38
    something we cannot control.
  • 10:39 - 10:44
    But a researcher at
    McGill University in Montreal,
  • 10:44 - 10:46
    called Amir Raz,
  • 10:46 - 10:52
    showed that this effect
    could actually be deautomatized.
  • 10:52 - 10:55
    So a very automatic effect like this one
  • 10:55 - 11:00
    can be deautomatized
    by hypnotic suggestion
  • 11:00 - 11:05
    to interpret this chain of letters
    as a meaningless chain.
  • 11:06 - 11:10
    Therefore, if we hypnotize
    one of the participants of the study,
  • 11:10 - 11:14
    telling them that this chain
    of words means nothing,
  • 11:14 - 11:18
    the automatic effect will be
    deautomatized and reduced.
  • 11:18 - 11:22
    This means that even some unconscious,
    highly automated processes
  • 11:22 - 11:24
    can be modified.
  • 11:25 - 11:30
    And so some of the behaviours
    we exhibit every day
  • 11:30 - 11:32
    that are highly automatic
  • 11:32 - 11:33
    are sometimes very useful,
  • 11:33 - 11:37
    like when driving, it's better
    not to continually ask ourselves questions
  • 11:37 - 11:42
    about what we need to do
    with the pedals, the gearbox, etc.,
  • 11:42 - 11:45
    at some point, it becomes
    very automatic and so much better,
  • 11:45 - 11:48
    while other behaviours
    we'd sometimes like to abandon,
  • 11:48 - 11:51
    like, for example,
    smoking 30 cigarettes a day,
  • 11:51 - 11:54
    or stuffing down a box of cookies we fancy
  • 11:54 - 11:57
    because we haven't the self-control -
  • 11:57 - 11:59
    these types of compulsions.
  • 12:01 - 12:07
    It shows, in fact, that these behaviours
    that have become automatized with time
  • 12:07 - 12:09
    can be deautomatized
  • 12:09 - 12:12
    to let us find again
    some sort of flexibility
  • 12:12 - 12:17
    and to expand the inventory
    of available actions.
  • 12:18 - 12:19
    So there.
  • 12:19 - 12:20
    So, to sum up,
  • 12:20 - 12:25
    there's the idea that neuroscience
    put to us to start out with
  • 12:25 - 12:28
    that our free will could be compromised
  • 12:28 - 12:32
    since, effectively, there are
    inconscient precursors to our actions
  • 12:32 - 12:35
    that we don't necessarily
    have control over,
  • 12:35 - 12:39
    and it would seem we are dictated to
    by these unconscious precursors.
  • 12:39 - 12:43
    But then neuroscience itself
    shows us round this:
  • 12:43 - 12:48
    attention is an essential ability we have
  • 12:48 - 12:52
    that modulates what will or will not
    enter our consciousness.
  • 12:52 - 12:57
    And so, I just wanted to show you
    that free will still exists,
  • 12:57 - 13:00
    but that it might be a bit more
    difficult to access it,
  • 13:00 - 13:05
    that it necessitates the long-term
    training of our attentional skills.
  • 13:05 - 13:09
    And I thank you for your attention.
  • 13:09 - 13:10
    (Applause)
Title:
Free will and neuroscience | Krystèle Appourchaux | TEDxMaussanelesAlpilles
Description:

What is our free will? The neurosciences do not grant us one; but is there still hope?

This talk was given at a TEDx event using the TED conference format but independently organized by a local community. Learn more at http://ted.com/tedx

more » « less
Video Language:
French
Team:
closed TED
Project:
TEDxTalks
Duration:
13:18

English subtitles

Revisions Compare revisions