Return to Video

PHILOSOPHY - Metaphysics: Paradoxes of Perception [HD]

  • 0:00 - 0:06
    (intro music)
  • 0:06 - 0:08
    Hi! I'm Eugen Fischer, senior lecturer in
  • 0:08 - 0:10
    philosophy at the University of East Anglia.
  • 0:10 - 0:13
    Today, we will look at some
    paradoxes about perception,
  • 0:13 - 0:15
    known as "arguments from illusion."
  • 0:15 - 0:20
    These arguments ask us to consider
    cases of non-veridical perception,
  • 0:20 - 0:23
    where something appears
    different than it is.
  • 0:23 - 0:28
    For example, when we look at round
    coins sideways, they appear elliptical.
  • 0:28 - 0:32
    Similarly, when seen from a
    greater distance, a man may
  • 0:32 - 0:36
    seem less than half as tall as another
    man of roughly equal height.
  • 0:36 - 0:38
    Or consider the phenomenon
    known as "refraction."
  • 0:38 - 0:40
    When a straight straw is partially
  • 0:40 - 0:42
    immersed in water, it looks bent.
  • 0:42 - 0:45
    All of these facts are
    familiar from daily life.
  • 0:45 - 0:47
    None of them is normally contested.
  • 0:47 - 0:51
    But these familiar facts seem to
    have a striking consequence.
  • 0:51 - 0:53
    They seem to imply that
    we are cut off from the
  • 0:53 - 0:57
    physical objects around us by
    a veil of experience within us.
  • 0:57 - 1:01
    The eighteenth-century philosopher David
    Hume drew this consequence very swiftly
  • 1:01 - 1:04
    when reflecting on another relevant fact:
  • 1:04 - 1:07
    as we all know, the table look
    smaller and smaller to people
  • 1:07 - 1:09
    the further away the move from it.
  • 1:09 - 1:12
    Hume observes that the
    table we see seems to
  • 1:12 - 1:16
    get smaller as we move away from it, yet
    there is no change in the size of the
  • 1:16 - 1:21
    real table, which is made of wood and
    stands in the parlor, regardless of
  • 1:21 - 1:22
    whether we look at it or not.
  • 1:22 - 1:26
    Hume immediately infers that
    we cannot be aware of this
  • 1:26 - 1:30
    unchanging, real table, and therefore
    must be aware of something else.
  • 1:30 - 1:34
    He concludes that thing we
    see is an image of the table,
  • 1:34 - 1:38
    whose size does change as we
    move away from the table.
  • 1:38 - 1:41
    This image then is present
    to us in our minds.
  • 1:41 - 1:44
    In other words, when you look at the table,
  • 1:44 - 1:48
    you are only aware of a mental
    image, not of the physical table.
  • 1:48 - 1:52
    To unpack this rather swift but
    historically influential argument,
  • 1:52 - 1:54
    let's have a closer look at the case of
  • 1:54 - 1:58
    the round coin that appears elliptical
    to you when you look at it sideways.
  • 1:58 - 2:01
    What exactly are you
    aware of in this case?
  • 2:01 - 2:02
    Describe your experience, rather
    than the objects around you.
  • 2:02 - 2:05
    Describe what you are aware of,
  • 2:05 - 2:10
    without making any judgment about the
    physical object you're facing, without
  • 2:10 - 2:12
    judging that object's shape, or size,
  • 2:12 - 2:15
    or color, or any other
    property of it.
  • 2:15 - 2:17
    That the right thing to
    say then, it seems,
  • 2:17 - 2:21
    is that you're aware of an
    elliptical, golden patch.
  • 2:21 - 2:24
    This judgment is often called
    the "phenomenal judgment."
  • 2:24 - 2:27
    The first step the argument elicits such
  • 2:27 - 2:29
    phenomenal judgments about cases of
  • 2:29 - 2:33
    non-veridical perception, like that
    of the coin or Hume's table.
  • 2:33 - 2:37
    The second step has us figure out what
    kind of thing we're then aware of.
  • 2:37 - 2:40
    What could that elliptical patch be?
  • 2:40 - 2:44
    It cannot be the coin, because the
    coin is round and not elliptical.
  • 2:44 - 2:47
    So you're clearly aware of
    something other than the coin.
  • 2:47 - 2:50
    Hume called this other thing an "image."
  • 2:50 - 2:55
    A now more common, and more
    neutral term, is "sense-datum."
  • 2:55 - 2:57
    Now continue to look in
    the direction of the coin.
  • 2:57 - 2:59
    How many different things do you see?
  • 2:59 - 3:01
    How many different things
    can you direct your
  • 3:01 - 3:04
    attention at and say
    that you are aware of?
  • 3:04 - 3:08
    Clearly, you cannot first direct your
    attention at something elliptical and
  • 3:08 - 3:10
    then shift your attention elsewhere to
  • 3:10 - 3:14
    become aware of something
    else that could be the coin.
  • 3:14 - 3:17
    So you are aware only
    of one thing, not of two.
  • 3:17 - 3:20
    We already concluded that you
    are aware the sense-datum.
  • 3:20 - 3:23
    Therefore, you cannot be
    aware of the coin too.
  • 3:23 - 3:27
    At any rate, not in the same way or sense.
  • 3:27 - 3:31
    But of course you are aware
    of the coin in some sense.
  • 3:31 - 3:33
    You know perfectly well that you are
  • 3:33 - 3:37
    looking at a coin rather than,
    say, a marble or a dice.
  • 3:37 - 3:42
    Proponents of the argument from illusion
    therefore commonly called the cautious
  • 3:42 - 3:46
    conclusion that the subjective sense-datum
    is the only thing you are directly aware of
  • 3:46 - 3:48
    when looking at the coin sideways.
  • 3:48 - 3:51
    At the same time, you may be indirectly
  • 3:51 - 3:54
    aware of the physical object, namely,
  • 3:54 - 3:58
    in virtue of being directly
    aware of the sense-datum.
  • 3:58 - 4:01
    So far, we have rehearsed the
    first half of the argument.
  • 4:01 - 4:05
    The second half then generalizes from
    the particular case of non-veridical
  • 4:05 - 4:09
    perception to all cases of perception.
  • 4:09 - 4:11
    This generalizing step builds on the
  • 4:11 - 4:13
    observation that sense data and physical
  • 4:13 - 4:17
    objects are the most radically
    different kinds of things.
  • 4:17 - 4:21
    For a start, the sense-datum is
    rather less stable than the coin.
  • 4:21 - 4:25
    The color patch changes its
    shape the moment you move,
  • 4:25 - 4:27
    while the coin retains its shape.
  • 4:27 - 4:33
    The sense-datum also vanishes the moment
    you close your eyes, while the coin vanishes
  • 4:33 - 4:35
    only the moment it gets melted down,
  • 4:35 - 4:38
    or some other major physical
    mishap occurs to it.
  • 4:38 - 4:43
    So the sense-datum and its properties
    depend upon you, the observer,
  • 4:43 - 4:49
    in ways in which the physical
    object and its properties do not.
  • 4:49 - 4:51
    Sense data are subjective, ever-changing,
  • 4:51 - 4:56
    and fleeting, like the flickering
    of a candle or its dying smoke.
  • 4:56 - 4:58
    Physical objects, by contrast, are
  • 4:58 - 5:02
    objective and stable, like
    solid tables and hard coins.
  • 5:02 - 5:04
    the intuitive key assumption now is
  • 5:04 - 5:08
    that our awareness of such radically
    different things should
  • 5:08 - 5:11
    constitute qualitatively
    different experiences.
  • 5:11 - 5:14
    We should be able to tell from
    the subjective quality of our
  • 5:14 - 5:19
    experience whether we are aware of a
    sense-datum or of a physical object.
  • 5:19 - 5:20
    But compare.
  • 5:20 - 5:24
    Have a look at this pencil, which
    is partially immersed in water.
  • 5:24 - 5:26
    To most people, it seems bent.
  • 5:26 - 5:29
    If you are like them, you are now directly
  • 5:29 - 5:33
    aware of a sense-datum or color
    patch, which actually is bent.
  • 5:33 - 5:35
    And now look at the pencil in the dry,
  • 5:35 - 5:39
    when it looks as straight
    as it actually is.
  • 5:39 - 5:40
    Can you tell any difference between the
  • 5:40 - 5:44
    subjective quality of one
    experience and the other?
  • 5:44 - 5:49
    Does one scene look, say, follier to
    you, or less clear, or more vivid?
  • 5:49 - 5:54
    Philosophers who find they cannot grow
    aware of any such difference like to
  • 5:54 - 5:59
    conclude that we must be aware of
    the same kind of thing in both cases.
  • 5:59 - 6:02
    So, if we are directly aware
    of a subjective sense-datum
  • 6:02 - 6:04
    in the case of non-veridical perception,
  • 6:04 - 6:07
    such a sense-datum is what
    we are directly aware of
  • 6:07 - 6:10
    also in the case of veridical perception.
  • 6:10 - 6:13
    When we use our eyes, all we are ever
  • 6:13 - 6:16
    directly aware of are
    subjective sense-data.
  • 6:16 - 6:20
    By sight, we are never directly
    aware of physical objects.
  • 6:20 - 6:22
    As we look around ourselves, we are cut
  • 6:22 - 6:24
    off from the physical objects
    in our environment
  • 6:24 - 6:27
    by a veil of subjective sense-data.
  • 6:27 - 6:30
    Other variants of the argument establish
  • 6:30 - 6:36
    analogous conclusions about the other
    senses: hearing, smell, taste, and touch.
  • 6:36 - 6:39
    Some other arguments, including
    arguments from hallucination,
  • 6:39 - 6:42
    lead from different premises
    to the same conclusions.
  • 6:42 - 6:46
    These conclusions seem to
    clash with common sense.
  • 6:46 - 6:51
    Surely, when we look at tables and
    chairs, we see these public, stable,
  • 6:51 - 6:53
    physical objects without further ado.
  • 6:53 - 6:56
    Surely, these objects are not blocked
  • 6:56 - 7:00
    from view by subjective, ever-changing
    objects of awareness.
  • 7:00 - 7:04
    Surely, we can just see tables and chairs,
  • 7:04 - 7:08
    without having to infer their
    presence around us from
  • 7:08 - 7:12
    subjective images, sense-data,
    or what have you.
  • 7:12 - 7:16
    By leading to a conclusion that clashes
    with our common sense conception
  • 7:16 - 7:18
    of perception, all these arguments
  • 7:18 - 7:22
    confront us with what is often simply
    called the "problem of perception."
  • 7:22 - 7:25
    We don't doubt that things sometimes
  • 7:25 - 7:28
    appear elliptical, yellow,
    bitter, or rough
  • 7:28 - 7:32
    when they actually are round,
    white, sweet, or smooth.
  • 7:32 - 7:34
    The present argument suggests
  • 7:34 - 7:36
    this implies that we cannot just see
  • 7:36 - 7:41
    or hear, smell or taste, or
    feel the things around us

  • 7:41 - 7:46
    This raises the problem: how is it
    possible for us to just see, or
  • 7:46 - 7:49
    otherwise perceive, the things
    in our physical environment
  • 7:49 - 7:52
    if these things often appear
    different than they are?
Title:
PHILOSOPHY - Metaphysics: Paradoxes of Perception [HD]
Description:

In this video, Dr Eugen Fischer (UEA) presents the ‘argument from illusion’. This argument appears to refute our common-sense conception of perception (seeing, hearing, etc.). Together with parallel arguments, it raises the problem of perception that has been a lynch-pin of Western philosophy, since the mid-18th century.

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Duration:
07:58

English subtitles

Revisions