1 00:00:01,083 --> 00:00:04,268 Every day we face issues like climate change 2 00:00:04,268 --> 00:00:05,708 or the safety of vaccines 3 00:00:05,708 --> 00:00:08,348 where we have to answer questions whose answers 4 00:00:08,348 --> 00:00:11,659 rely heavily on scientific information. 5 00:00:11,659 --> 00:00:15,033 Scientists tell us that the world is warming. 6 00:00:15,033 --> 00:00:17,281 Scientists tell us that vaccines are safe. 7 00:00:17,281 --> 00:00:19,465 But how do we know if they are right? 8 00:00:19,465 --> 00:00:21,569 Why should be believe the science? 9 00:00:21,569 --> 00:00:24,898 The fact is, many of us actually don't believe the science. 10 00:00:24,898 --> 00:00:27,314 Public opinion polls consistently show 11 00:00:27,314 --> 00:00:29,634 that significant proportions of the American people 12 00:00:29,634 --> 00:00:33,225 don't believe the climate is warming due to human activities, 13 00:00:33,225 --> 00:00:36,724 don't think that there is evolution by natural selection, 14 00:00:36,724 --> 00:00:40,805 and aren't persuaded by the safety of vaccines. 15 00:00:40,805 --> 00:00:44,316 So why should we believe the science? 16 00:00:44,316 --> 00:00:47,957 Well, scientists don't like talking about science as a matter of belief. 17 00:00:47,957 --> 00:00:50,444 In fact, they would contract science with faith, 18 00:00:50,444 --> 00:00:53,068 and they would say belief is the domain of faith. 19 00:00:53,068 --> 00:00:57,238 And faith is a separate thing apart and distinct from science. 20 00:00:57,238 --> 00:00:59,790 Indeed they would say religion is based on faith 21 00:00:59,790 --> 00:01:04,254 or maybe the calculous of Pascal's wager. 22 00:01:04,254 --> 00:01:07,110 Blaise Pascal was a 17th century mathematician 23 00:01:07,110 --> 00:01:09,630 who tried to bring scientific reasoning to the question of 24 00:01:09,630 --> 00:01:11,542 whether or not he should believe in God, 25 00:01:11,542 --> 00:01:13,616 and his wager went like this: 26 00:01:13,616 --> 00:01:15,935 well, if God doesn't exist 27 00:01:15,935 --> 00:01:18,595 but I decide to believe in him 28 00:01:18,595 --> 00:01:20,538 nothing much is really lost. 29 00:01:20,538 --> 00:01:22,451 Maybe a few hours on Sunday. 30 00:01:22,451 --> 99:59:59,999 [Laughter] 31 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But if he does exist and I don't believe in him, 32 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 then I'm in deep trouble. 33 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And so Pascal said, we'd better believe in God. 34 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Or as one of my college professors said, 35 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 "he clutched for the handmill of faith". 36 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 He made that leap of faith 37 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 leaving science and rationalism behind. 38 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Now the fact is though, for most of us 39 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 most scientific claims are a leap of faith. 40 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 We can't really judge scientific claims for ourselves in most cases. 41 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And indeed this is actually true for most scientists as well 42 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 outside of their own specialties. 43 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So if you think about it, a geologist can't tell you 44 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 wether a vaccine is safe. 45 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Most chemists are not experts in evolutionary theory. 46 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 A physicist cannot tell you, despite the claims of some of them, 47 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 wether or not tobacco causes cancer. 48 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So, if even scientists themselves have to make a leap of faith 49 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 outside their own fields, 50 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 then why do they accept the claims of other scientists? 51 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Why do they believe each other's claims? 52 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And should we believe those claims? 53 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So what I'd like to argue is yes, we should. 54 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But not for the reason that most of us think. 55 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Most of us were taught in school that the reason we should 56 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 believe in science is because of the scientific method. 57 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 We were taught that scientists follow a method 58 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and that this method guarantees the truth of their claims. 59 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The method that most of us were taught in school, 60 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we can call it the text book method, 61 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is the hypo-deductive method. 62 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 According to the standard model, the textbook model, 63 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 scientists develop hypotheses, they deduce the 64 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 consequences for those hypotheses, 65 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and then they go out into the world and they say: 66 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Are those consequences true? 67 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Can we observe them taking place in the natural world? 68 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And if they are true, then the scientists say: 69 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Great, we know the hypothesis is correct. 70 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So there are many famous examples in the history 71 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of science of scientists doing exactly this. 72 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 One of the most famous examples 73 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 comes from the work of Albert Einstein. 74 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 When Einstein developed the theory of general relativity 75 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 one of the consequences of his theory 76 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 was that space time wasn't just an empty void 77 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but that it actually had a fabric. 78 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And that that fabric was bent 79 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 in the presence of massive objects like the sun. 80 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So if this theory were true then it meant that light 81 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 as it passed the sun 82 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 should actually be bent around it. 83 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 That was a pretty startling prediction 84 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and it took a few years before scientists 85 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 were able to test it. 86 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But they did test it in 1919 87 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and low and behold it turned out to be true. 88 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Starlight actually does bend as it travels around the sun. 89 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 This was a huge confirmation of the theory. 90 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It was considered proof of the truth of this radical new idea 91 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and it was written up in many newspapers around the globe. 92 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Now sometimes this theory or this model 93 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is referred to as the deductive-nomological model. 94 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Meaning those academics like to make things complicated. [Laughter] 95 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But also because in the ideal case it's about laws. 96 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So nomological means having to do with laws. 97 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And in the ideal case, the hypothesis isn't just an idea, 98 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 ideally it is a law of nature. 99 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Why does it matter that it is a law of nature? 100 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Because if it is a law, it can't be broken. 101 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 If it's a law then it will always be true 102 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 in all times and all places 103 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 no matter what the circumstances are. 104 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And all of you know at least one example of a famous law. 105 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Einstein's famous equation, E=MC2, 106 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 which tells us what the relationship is 107 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 between energy and mass. 108 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And that relationship is true no matter what. 109 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It turns out though that there are several problems with this model. 110 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The main problem is that it's wrong. 111 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's just not true. [Laughter] 112 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And I'm going to talk about three reasons why it's wrong. 113 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So the first reason is a logical reason, 114 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 it's the problem of the fallacy of affirming the consequent. 115 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So that's another fancy academic way of saying 116 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that false theories can make true predictions. 117 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So just because the prediction comes true 118 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 doesn't actually logically prove that the theory is correct. 119 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And I have a good example of that too, again from the history of science. 120 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 This is a picture of the Ptolemaic universe 121 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 with the Earth at the center of the universe 122 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and The Sun and the planets going around it. 123 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The Ptolemaic model was believed 124 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 by many very smart people for many centuries. 125 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well why? 126 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well the answer is because it made lots of predictions that came true. 127 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The Ptolemaic system enabled astronomers 128 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to make accurate predictions of the motions of the planet. 129 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In fact more accurate predictions at first 130 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 than the Copernican theory which we now would say is true. 131 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So that's one problem with the textbook model, 132 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a second problem is a practical problem 133 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and it's the problem of auxiliary hypotheses. 134 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Auxiliary hypotheses are assumptions 135 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that scientists are making, 136 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that they may or may not even be aware that they're making. 137 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So an important example of this comes from 138 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 comes from the Copernican model 139 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 which ultimately replaced the Ptolemaic system. 140 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So when Nicolaus Copernicus said, 141 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 actually the Earth is not the center of the universe, 142 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the sun is the center of the solar system, 143 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the Earth moves around the sun. 144 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists said, well okay, Nicolaus, if that's true 145 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we ought to be able to detect the motion 146 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of the Earth around the sun. 147 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And so this slide here illustrates a concept 148 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 known as stellar parallax. 149 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And astronomers said, if the Earth is moving 150 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and we look at a prominent star, let's say, Sirius. 151 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well I know I'm in Manhattan so you guys can't see the stars, 152 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but imagine you're out in the country, imagine you chose that rural life. 153 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And we look at a star in December, we see that star 154 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 against the backdrop of distant stars. 155 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 If we now make the same observation six months later 156 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 when the Earth has moved to this position in June, 157 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we look at that same star and we see it against a different backdrop. 158 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 That difference, that angular difference, is the stellar parallax. 159 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So this is the prediction that the Copernican model makes, 160 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 astronomers looked for the stellar parallax 161 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and they found nothing, nothing at all. 162 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And many people argued that this proved that the Copernican model was false. 163 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So what happened? 164 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well in hindsight we can say that astronomers were making 165 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 two auxiliary hypotheses, both of which 166 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we would now say were incorrect. 167 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The first was an assumption about the size of the Earth's orbit. 168 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Astronomers were assuming that the Earth's orbit was large 169 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 relative to the stars. 170 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Today we would draw the picture more like this, 171 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 this comes from NASA, 172 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and you see the Earth's orbit is actually quite small. 173 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In fact, it's actually much smaller even than shown here. 174 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The stellar parallax therefore, 175 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is very small and actually very hard to detect. 176 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And that leads to the second reason 177 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 why the prediction didn't work, 178 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because scientists were also assuming 179 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that the telescopes they had were sensitive enough 180 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to detect the parallax. 181 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And that turned out not to be true. 182 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It wasn't until the 19th century that scientists were able to detect 183 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the stellar parallax. 184 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So, there's a third problem as well. 185 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The third problem is simply a factual problem 186 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that a lot of science doesn't fit the textbook model. 187 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 A lot of science isn't deductive at all, it's actually inductive. 188 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And by that we mean that scientists don't necessarily 189 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 start with theories and hypotheses, often they just 190 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 start with observations of stuff going on in the world. 191 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And the most famous example of that is one of the most 192 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 famous scientists who ever lived, Charles Darwin. 193 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 When Darwin went out as a young man on the voyage of the Beagle, 194 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 he didn't have a hypothesis, he didn't have a theory. 195 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 He just knew that he wanted to have a career as a scientist 196 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and he started to collect data. 197 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Mainly he knew that he hated medicine 198 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because the sight of blood made him sick so 199 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 he had to have an alternative career path. 200 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So he started collecting data. 201 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And he collected many things including his famous finches. 202 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 When he collected these finches he through them in a bag 203 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and he had no idea what they meant. 204 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Many years later back in London, 205 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Darwin looked at his data again and began to develop 206 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 an explanation 207 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and that explanation was the theory of natural selection. 208 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Besides inductive science, 209 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 scientists also often participate in modeling. 210 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 One of the things scientists want to do in life 211 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is to explain the causes of things. 212 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And how do we do that? 213 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well, one way you can do it is to build a model 214 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that tests an idea. 215 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So this is a picture of Henry Cadell, 216 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 who was a Scottish geologist in the 19th century. 217 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 You can tell he's Scottish because he's wearing 218 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a deerstalker cap and Wellington boots. 219 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 (Laughter) 220 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And Cadell wanted to answer the question, 221 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 how are mountains formed? 222 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And one of the things he had observed 223 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is that if you look at mountains like the Appalachians, 224 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 you often find that the rocks in them 225 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 are folded, 226 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and they're folded in a particular way, 227 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 which suggested to him 228 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that they were actually being compressed from the side. 229 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And this idea would later play a major role 230 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 in discussions of continental drift. 231 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So he built this model, this crazy contraption 232 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 with levers and wood and here's his wheelbarrow, 233 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 buckets, a big sledgehammer. 234 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 I don't know why he's got the Wellington boots. 235 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Maybe it's going to rain. 236 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And he created this physical model in order 237 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to demonstrate that you could in fact create 238 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 patterns in rocks, or at least in this case in mud, 239 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that looked a lot like mountains 240 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if you compressed them from the side. 241 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So it was an argument about the cause of mountains. 242 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Nowadays, most scientists prefer to work inside, 243 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 so they don't build physical models so much 244 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 as to make computer simulations. 245 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But a computer simulation is a kind of a model. 246 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's a model that's made with mathematics, 247 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and like the physical models of the 19th century, 248 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 it's very important for thinking about causes. 249 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So one of the big questions to do with climate change, 250 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we have tremendous amounts of evidence 251 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that the earth is warming up. 252 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 This slide here, the black line shows 253 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the measurements that scientists have taken 254 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 for the last 150 years 255 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 showing that the earth's temperature 256 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 has steadily increased, 257 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and you can see in particular that in the last 50 years 258 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 there's been this dramatic increase 259 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of nearly one degree Centigrade, 260 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 or almost two degrees Fahrenheit. 261 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So what, though, is driving that change? 262 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 How can we know what's causing 263 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the observed warming? 264 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well, scientists can model it 265 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 using a computer simulation. 266 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So this diagram illustrates a computer simulation 267 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that has looked at all the different factors 268 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that we know can influence the earth's climate, 269 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 so sulfate particles from air pollution, 270 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 volcanic dust from volcanic eruptions, 271 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 changes in solar radiation, 272 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and, of course, greenhouse gases. 273 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And they asked the question, 274 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what set of variables put into a model 275 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 will reproduce what we actually see in real life? 276 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So here is the real life in black. 277 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Here's the model in this light grey, 278 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and the answer is 279 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a model that includes, it's the answer E on that SAT, 280 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 all of the above. 281 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The only way you can reproduce 282 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the observed temperature measurements 283 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is with all of these things put together, 284 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 including greenhouse gases, 285 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and in particular you can see that the increase 286 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 in greenhouse gases tracks 287 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 this very dramatic increase in temperature 288 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 over the last 50 years. 289 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And so this is why climate scientists say 290 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 it's not just that we know that climate change is happening, 291 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 we know that greenhouse gases are a major part 292 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of the reason why. 293 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So now because there all these different things 294 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that scientists do, 295 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the philosopher Paul Feyerabend famously said, 296 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 "The only principle in science 297 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that doesn't inhibit progress is: anything goes." 298 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Now this quotation has often been taken out of context, 299 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because Feyerabend was not actually saying 300 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that in science anything goes. 301 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 What he was saying was, 302 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 actually the full quotation is, 303 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 "If you press me to say 304 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what is the method of science, 305 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 I would have to say: anything goes." 306 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 What he was trying to say 307 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is that scientists do a lot of different things. 308 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists are creative. 309 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But then this pushes the question back: 310 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if scientists don't use a single method, 311 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 then how do they decide 312 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what's right and what's wrong? 313 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And who judges? 314 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And the answer is, scientists judge, 315 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and they judge by judging evidence. 316 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists collect evidence in many different ways, 317 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but however they collect it, 318 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 they have to subject it to scrutiny. 319 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And this led to sociologist Robert Merton 320 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to focus on this question of how scientists 321 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 scrutinize data and evidence, 322 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and he said they do it in a way he called 323 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 "organized skepticism." 324 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And by that he meant it's organized 325 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because they do it collectively, 326 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 they do it as a group, 327 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and skepticism, because they do it from a position 328 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of distrust. 329 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 That is to say, the burden of proof 330 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is on the person with a novel claim. 331 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And in this sense, science is intrinsically conservative. 332 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's quite hard to persuade the scientific community 333 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to say, "Yes, we know something, this is true." 334 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So despite the popularity of the concept 335 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of paradigm shifts, 336 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what we find is that actually, 337 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 really major changes in scientific thinking 338 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 are relatively rare in the history of science. 339 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So finally that brings us to one more idea: 340 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if scientists judge evidence collectively, 341 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 this has led historians to focus on the question 342 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of consensus, 343 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and to say that at the end of the day, 344 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what science is, 345 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 what scientific knowledge is, 346 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is the consensus of the scientific experts 347 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 who through this process of organized scrutiny, 348 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 collective scrutiny, 349 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 have judged the evidence 350 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and come to a conclusion about it, 351 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 either yea or nay. 352 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So we can think of scientific knowledge 353 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 as a consensus of experts. 354 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 We can also think of science as being 355 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a kind of a jury, 356 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 except it's a very special kind of jury. 357 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's not a jury of your peers, 358 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 it's a jury of geeks. 359 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's a jury of men and women with Ph.D's, 360 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and unlike a conventional jury, 361 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 which has only two choices, 362 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 guilty or not guilty, 363 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the scientific jury actually has a number of choices. 364 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists can say yes, something's true. 365 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists can say no, it's false. 366 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Or, they can say, well it might be true 367 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but we need to work more and collect more evidence. 368 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Or, they can say it might be true, 369 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but we don't know how to answer the question 370 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and we're going to put it aside 371 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and maybe come back to it later. 372 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 That's what scientists call "intractable." 373 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But this leads us to one final problem: 374 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if science is what scientists say it is, 375 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 then isn't that just an appeal to authority? 376 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And weren't we all taught in school 377 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that the appeal to authority is a logical fallacy? 378 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well, here's the paradox of modern science, 379 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the paradox of the conclusions I think historians 380 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and philosophers and sociologists have come to, 381 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that actually science is the appeal to authority, 382 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but it's not the authority of the individual, 383 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 no matter how smart that individual is, 384 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 like Plato or Socrates or Einstein. 385 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's the authority of the collective community. 386 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 You can think of it is a kind of wisdom of the crowd, 387 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but a very special kind of crowd. 388 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Science does appeal to authority, 389 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but it's not based on any individual, 390 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 no matter how smart that individual may be. 391 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's based on the collective wisdom, 392 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the collective knowledge, the collective work, 393 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of all of the scientists who have worked 394 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on a particular problem. 395 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Scientists have a kind of culture of collective distrust, 396 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 this "show me" culture, 397 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 illustrated by this nice woman here 398 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 showing her colleagues her evidence. 399 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Of course, these people don't really look like scientists, 400 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because they're much too happy. 401 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 (Laughter) 402 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Okay, so that brings me to my final point. 403 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Most of us get up in the morning. 404 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Most of us trust our cars. 405 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Well, see, now I think, I'm in Manhattan, 406 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 this is a bad analogy, 407 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but most Americans who don't live in Manhattan 408 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 get up in the morning and get in their cars 409 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and turn on that ignition, and their cars work, 410 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and they work incredibly well. 411 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The modern automobile hardly ever breaks down. 412 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 So why is that? Why do cars work so well? 413 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's not because of the genius of Henry Ford 414 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 or Carl Benz or even Elon Musk. 415 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 It's because the modern automobile 416 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 is the product of more than 100 years of work 417 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 by hundreds and thousands 418 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and tens of thousands of people. 419 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The modern automobile is the product 420 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of the collected work and wisdom and experience 421 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of every man and woman who has ever worked 422 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on a car, 423 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and the reliability of the technology is the result 424 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of that accumulated effort. 425 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 We benefit not just from the benefit of Benz 426 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and Ford and Musk 427 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but from the collective intelligence and hard work 428 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 of all of the people who have worked 429 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on the modern car. 430 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And the same is true of science, 431 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 only science is even older. 432 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Our basis for trust in science is actually the same 433 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 as our basis in trust in technology, 434 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and the same as our basis for trust in anything, 435 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 namely, experience. 436 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But it shouldn't be blind trust 437 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 anymore than we would have blind trust in anything. 438 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Our trust in science, like science itself, 439 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 should be based on evidence, 440 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and that means that scientists 441 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 have to become better communicators. 442 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They have to explain to us not just what they know 443 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but how they know it, 444 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and it means that we have to become better listeners. 445 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Thank you very much. 446 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 (Applause)