0:00:05.650,0:00:08.513 My name is Jennifer Nagel. 0:00:09.020,0:00:11.011 I teach philosophy at the university of Toronto, 0:00:11.450,0:00:13.692 and today I want to talk to you about knowledge. 0:00:13.901,0:00:17.312 Knowledge is something human beings naturally crave, 0:00:17.312,0:00:19.081 we spend a lot of time and effort 0:00:19.081,0:00:21.252 trying to gain it, for example by 0:00:21.252,0:00:22.801 watching videos like this one. 0:00:23.391,0:00:25.550 We also have natural instincts to keep 0:00:25.550,0:00:27.929 track of what other people do and don't know 0:00:27.930,0:00:30.632 in order to make sense of what they're doing. 0:00:31.188,0:00:33.508 But it's suprisingly difficult to give a good 0:00:33.512,0:00:36.979 explanation of the nature of knowledge itself, 0:00:36.979,0:00:38.919 and to say how knowing that something is 0:00:38.919,0:00:41.837 true, differs from just thinking that it's true. 0:00:42.803,0:00:45.028 When we try to figure out what knowledge is, 0:00:45.028,0:00:47.474 we encounter some interesting questions 0:00:47.474,0:00:51.333 and paradoxes. This series explores these problems, 0:00:51.333,0:00:54.519 and explains how philosophers have tried to solve them. 0:00:54.958,0:00:57.644 This particular video will focus on some basic 0:00:57.644,0:01:00.074 features of knowledge, features that any good 0:01:00.074,0:01:02.424 theory of it should try to explain. 0:01:02.970,0:01:05.694 So, what kinds of things can you know? 0:01:06.463,0:01:09.198 The english verb "know" is used in several ways; 0:01:09.509,0:01:12.549 you can know a person, "Alice knows Pierre"; 0:01:12.638,0:01:15.418 a place, "Pierre knows Paris"; 0:01:15.418,0:01:17.899 or a language, "Alice knows french". 0:01:18.449,0:01:20.744 But the most common way of using the verb 0:01:20.744,0:01:23.409 "to know" is the way we use it when we're 0:01:23.419,0:01:26.307 speaking of someone knowing a fact, as in 0:01:26.756,0:01:28.979 "Alice knows that it's raining outside". 0:01:29.318,0:01:32.621 In this series we'll be focusing on this 0:01:32.621,0:01:36.318 knowing-a-fact sense of the verb "to know". 0:01:37.248,0:01:39.667 Sometimes this is called "knowledge-that", 0:01:39.887,0:01:43.299 but actually, along with "that", you can use 0:01:43.299,0:01:45.773 question words like "where" or "when". 0:01:46.059,0:01:49.139 "Pierre knows when the party will start" 0:01:49.430,0:01:52.489 or "Pierre knows where the party is". 0:01:52.732,0:01:55.666 Knowing where the party is means knowing the 0:01:55.666,0:01:58.468 answer to the question "where's the party?", 0:01:58.468,0:02:01.609 and that's going to be a fact, like the fact 0:02:01.609,0:02:04.589 that the party is at Alice's place. Knowledge is 0:02:04.589,0:02:07.358 a way of being latched on to a fact. 0:02:08.719,0:02:10.723 It is thought that every language in the world 0:02:10.723,0:02:13.711 has a word that works to translate this fact-grabbing 0:02:13.711,0:02:16.153 sense of the word "to know". 0:02:16.313,0:02:19.430 And this kind of global popularity is very rare, 0:02:19.454,0:02:21.703 only about a hundred words are thought 0:02:21.703,0:02:23.833 to be universal in this way. 0:02:24.274,0:02:27.244 Around the world, words meaning "to know" are 0:02:27.266,0:02:30.505 also very heavily used. It's one of the top ten 0:02:30.507,0:02:33.456 most common words in english for example. 0:02:34.154,0:02:36.803 So we often find ourselves talking about 0:02:36.803,0:02:39.613 knowledge, but when we say someone knows 0:02:39.613,0:02:42.019 something, what do we mean? 0:02:42.762,0:02:45.501 It can help to compare knowing and just believing. 0:02:46.171,0:02:48.354 Consider these two sentences: 0:02:48.779,0:02:52.243 1. "Alice knows that it's raining outside." 0:02:52.662,0:02:56.402 2. "Pierre believes that it's raining outside." 0:02:57.154,0:03:00.023 We instinctively feel some difference between 0:03:00.024,0:03:02.347 Alice and Pierre, but what is it? 0:03:02.687,0:03:05.383 Actually, we'll see there's several possible 0:03:05.383,0:03:07.094 points of contrast here. 0:03:07.632,0:03:10.010 The first and easiest has to do with truth. 0:03:10.682,0:03:13.301 If Pierre just believes that it's raining outside, 0:03:13.301,0:03:16.281 where he is, maybe he's wrong. Maybe the 0:03:16.291,0:03:18.211 rain has stopped, and he's fooled by the 0:03:18.221,0:03:20.872 sound of water dripping from the trees. 0:03:21.541,0:03:24.280 The things we believe are sometimes true 0:03:24.280,0:03:25.681 and sometimes false. 0:03:26.191,0:03:28.192 What we actually know on the other hand, 0:03:28.192,0:03:33.031 has to be true, or factual. So there's no problem saying 0:03:33.031,0:03:35.503 "Pierre believes it's raining, but it isn't." 0:03:35.523,0:03:37.022 While it sounds weird to say 0:03:37.022,0:03:39.501 "Alice knows it's raining, but it isn't." 0:03:39.501,0:03:42.366 This is because attachment to the truth 0:03:42.366,0:03:44.847 is built into the meaning of knows-that. 0:03:45.365,0:03:47.997 Beyond truth, another key feature of 0:03:47.997,0:03:49.776 knowledge is confidence. 0:03:49.826,0:03:51.556 Let's suppose that Pierre is in a windowless 0:03:51.556,0:03:54.017 room, and he's been there for an hour. 0:03:54.322,0:03:56.481 He could suspect that it's still raining 0:03:56.481,0:03:58.812 outside, even of he's not totally sure. 0:03:59.092,0:04:01.881 But if Alice knows that it's raining, she has 0:04:01.901,0:04:03.542 no doubt. She's confident. 0:04:04.292,0:04:07.653 So, is confident belief in a truth enough 0:04:07.653,0:04:10.041 for knowing? Apparently not. 0:04:10.756,0:04:13.076 There's at least one more thing we need. 0:04:13.786,0:04:17.496 Imagine that Pierre is really pessimistic, 0:04:17.496,0:04:19.586 he's always strongly convinced that 0:04:19.586,0:04:22.102 things will go badly. He's often wrong, 0:04:22.102,0:04:25.746 but sometimes he's right. Today he wakes up 0:04:25.746,0:04:28.758 in a windowless room, aware that Alice has 0:04:28.758,0:04:31.297 planned a picnic because the forecast was 0:04:31.297,0:04:34.616 for sunny weather. "It's going to be terrible", 0:04:34.616,0:04:38.957 he thinks. "I'm sure it's already raining right now". 0:04:40.107,0:04:43.277 He's entirely confident that it's raining, 0:04:43.297,0:04:45.897 although he can't actually see or hear the rain. 0:04:46.268,0:04:48.698 And let's say by chance it turns out he's 0:04:48.698,0:04:51.897 right this time. Does Pierre actually know 0:04:51.897,0:04:53.937 that it's raining outside? 0:04:54.132,0:04:57.105 If he doesn't know, then it seems knowledge 0:04:57.105,0:04:59.815 requires something more than confident 0:04:59.815,0:05:03.575 belief in a truth. Feeling pessimistic isn't 0:05:03.575,0:05:06.035 a good basis for judgements about the weather. 0:05:06.628,0:05:08.986 Your judgement needs to have a good basis 0:05:08.986,0:05:10.755 in order to count as knowledge. 0:05:11.448,0:05:14.387 But what kind of basis counts as good? 0:05:15.154,0:05:17.446 Do you have to be standing outside, 0:05:17.446,0:05:20.268 getting wet? As you will see, 0:05:20.268,0:05:22.527 in the upcoming videos on the analysis of 0:05:22.527,0:05:25.179 knowledge, this is a controversial question. 0:05:25.876,0:05:28.328 But before we get to that problem, we'll 0:05:28.328,0:05:32.598 tackle a more basic problem: is knowledge even 0:05:32.703,0:05:35.913 possible for us? Even in the best case 0:05:35.913,0:05:38.318 scenario, when it feels like you're standing 0:05:38.318,0:05:40.565 right outside, right in the rain, can you 0:05:40.565,0:05:42.709 really know that it's raining outside? 0:05:43.560,0:05:46.220 Could you be dreaming for example, 0:05:46.220,0:05:47.571 on a clear night? 0:05:48.330,0:05:50.541 This is the problem of skepticism, 0:05:50.541,0:05:53.000 explored in the next video. 0:05:53.000,0:05:55.690 The two following videos will explain 0:05:55.690,0:05:58.374 possible solutions to skepticism.