Chương trình được tài trợ bởi: Tài trợ phụ bởi lần trước chúng ta đã tranh luận về trường hợp vụ Nữ hoàng kiện Dudley và Stephens vụ đắm tàu, vụ ăn thịt người trên biển và với những lập luận về vụ đắm tàu, những lập luận ủng hộ và chống lại những suy nghĩ của Dudley và Stephens, hãy quay trở lại với vấn đề triết học triết học vị lợi của Jeremy Bentham Bentham sinh ra ở Anh năm 1748, 12 tuổi ông vào học Oxford, 15 tuổi ông học trường luật. ông được nhận vào đoàn luật sư năm 19 tuổi, nhưng anh ta chưa bao giờ hành nghề luật sư, thay vào đó, ông dâng trọn đời mình cho Luật học và Triết học đạo đức. lần trước chúng ta đã bắt đầu xem xét một phiên bản về thuyết vị lợi của Bentham ý tưởng chính đơn giản được phát biểu như thế này, nguyên tắc tối cao của đạo đức, cho dù là đạo đức cá nhân hay đạo đức chính trị Đều là tối đa hóa phúc lợi chung hay hạnh phúc của tập thể, hay sự cân bằng tổng thể giữa niềm vui và nỗi thống khổ Nói cách khác là tối đa hóa tính có ích Bentham đưa ra nguyên tắc này bằng dòng lập luận rằng, tất cả chúng ta đều bị chi phối bởi nỗi đau và niềm vui chúng là những bậc thầy tối cao của chúng ta, và do vậy bất kỳ hệ thống đạo đức nào cũng phải tính đến chúng. Tính như thế nào là tốt nhất? Bằng cách tối đa hóa và điều này dẫn đến nguyên tắc rằng lợi ích lớn nhất cho nhiều người nhất Vậy chính xác chúng ta nên tối đã hóa tiện ích gì? Bentham nói với chúng ta đó là hạnh phúc hay chính xác hơn là tính có ích. tính có ích. Tối đa hóa tiện ích là một nguyên tắc không chỉ cho cá nhân mà còn cho cộng đồng, và Cả đối với các nhà lập pháp, cuối cùng là cho cả mốt cuộc cộng đồng mà Bentham yêu cầu đó là tổng thể các cá nhân bao gồm trong đó, và đó là lý do trong việc quyết định chính sách tốt nhất, trong việc quyết định luật lệ nên như thế nào, trong việc quyết định điều gì là công bằng, công dân và các nhà lập pháp nên hỏi chính bản thân họ câu hỏi, rằng nếu chúng ta cộng hết, tất cả những lợi ích của chính sách này, rồi trừ đi tất cả các chi phí, việc đúng nên làm là cái mà tối đa hóa được sự cân bằng giữa hạnh phúc và đau khổ. Đó là ý nghĩa của việc tối đa hóa tiện ích Bây giờ, ngày hôm nay tôi muốn xem liệu các bạn đồng ý hay không đồng ý với điều đó, và suy luận vị lợi này thường diễn ra dưới cái tên phân tích phí tổn - lợi ích Thường xuyên được sử dụng bởi các công ty và bởi chính phủ Và nó luôn luôn l iên quan đến việc đặt một giá trị - thường là giá trị tiền bạc - để đại diện cho tính có lợi ích Dựa trên chi phí và lợi ích của nhiều đề xuất khác nhau. Mới gần đây, ở Cộng hòa Séc, có một đề xuất tăng thuế tiêu thụ đặc biệt đối với thuốc lá Philip Morris, Một công ty thuốc lá, doanh thu khổng lồ Ở Cộng hòa Séc. Họ đã thực hiện một nghiên cứu về phân tích lợi ích - chi phí Của việc hút thuốc lá ở Cộng hòa Séc. Và phân tích lợi ích chi phí của họ Cho thấy rằng chính phủ sẽ có lợi bằng việc có công dân Séc hút thuốc lá. Bây giờ, hãy xem xem chính phủ đạt được lợi ích như thế nào? Đúng là việc này có những tác động tiêu cực cho tài chính công của chính phủ Séc bởi vì có sự gia tăng chi phí chăm sóc sức khỏe cho những người mắc các bệnh liên quan đến hút thuốc Mặc khác, những bệnh tật này lại tạo ra những tác động tích cực và tất cả đã được cộng dồn lại ở phái bên kia sổ cái những tác động tích cực bao gồm, chủ yếu là các nguồn thu thuế khác nhau mà chính phủ thu được từ doanh số bán các sản phẩm thuốc lá, nhưng còn gồm cả khoản tiết kiệm được từ chi phí chăm sóc sức khỏe chính phủ không phải chi trả khi người ta chết sớm tiết kiệm lương hưu, bạn không phải trả lương hưu trong thời gian dài, và cả tiết kiệm được tiết kiệm chi phí nhà ở cho người già. Và khi tất cả các chi phí và lợi ích được cộng dồn lại nghiên cứu của Philip Morris cho thấy rằng tài chính công ở Cộng hòa Séc có một khoản thu ròng 147 triệu đô la và còn tiết kiệm được và tiết kiệm được chi phí nhà ở, chăm sóc sức khỏe và lương hưu. Chính phủ được hưởng khoản tiết kiệm hơn 1.200 đô la khi mỗi người chết sớm vì hút thuốc. phân tích chi phí - lợi ích, ngay bây giờ, trong số những bạn ủng hộ thuyết vị lợi có thể nghĩ rằng đây là một cuộc kiểm tra không công bằng. khảo nghiệm của Philip Morris đã bị báo chí chỉ trích và họ đã phải xin lỗi vì phép tính vô nhân đạo này bạn có thể nói rằng điều thiếu sót ở đây là thứ mà thuyết vị lợi có thể dễ dàng kết nối lại với nhau chủ yếu là giá trị đối với con người và gia đình của những người đã qua đời vì ung thư phổi. Thế còn giá trị của mạng sống thì sao? Một số phân tích lợi ích - chi phí kết hợp cả thước đo giá trị cuộc sống. Một trong những vụ nổi tiếng nhất trong số đó liên quan đến vụ xe Ford Pinto Các bạn đã đọc về vụ đó không? Trở lại vào những năm 1970, chắc các bạn vẫn nhớ mẫu xe Ford Pinto, đó là một loại xe hơi? Có ai còn nhớ không? đó là một mẫu xe nhỏ, xe ô tô nhỏ, rất phổ biến nhưng có một vấn đề là bình xăng nằm phía sau xe và thực tế trong những vụ va chạm từ phía sau, bình xăng đã phát nổ Và, một số người đã thiệt mạng, một số người bị thương nặng. nạn nhân của những vụ tai nạn này đã kiện hãng Ford ra tòa, và trong phiên tòa, hóa ra Ford đã biết từ rất lâu trước đó về bình xăng dễ bị nổ và đã thực hiện phân tích lợi ích - chi phí để xác định liệu có đáng để đặt một tấm chắn đặc biệt để bảo vệ bình xăng và ngăn nó phát nổ không. Họ đã làm một phân tích lợi ích - chi phí chi phí cho mỗi phần để tăng độ an toàn của chiếc Pinto, họ đã tính toán ra tầm 11 đô la cho mỗi bộ phận và đây, đây là phân tích - lợi ích chi phí được đưa ra ở phiên xét xử, Mỗi bộ phận 11 đô la cho 12,5 triệu chiếc xe hơi và xe tải nên tổng chi phí là 137 triệu đô la để cải thiện sự an toàn nhưng sau đó họ đã tính toán lợi ích của việc tiêu tất cả số tiền này để có một mẫu xe an toàn hơn và họ đếm được 180 người chết và quy ra giá trị bằng tiền 200 nghìn đô la cho mỗi người chết, 180 người bị thương nhận 67 nghìn đô la, và tiếp đó là chi phí sửa chữa, thay thế cho 2000 chiếc xe bị phá hủy nếu không có thiết bị an toàn. 700 đô la mỗi xe. Như vậy, hóa ra những lợi ích chỉ khoảng 49,5 triệu. Thế nên họ đã không lắp đặt thiết bị an toàn. Không cần phải nói khi bản ghi nhớ về phân tích lợi ích-chi phí của Công ty Ford Motor được đưa ra trong buổi xét xử nó khiến bồi thẩm viên kinh hoàng. Và họ đã yêu cầu một khoản phạt khổng lồ Liệu đây có phải là một ví dụ đi ngược lại với ý tưởng vị lợi khi tính toán vì Ford đã đưa vào phép tính thước đo giá trị của mạng sống? Bây giờ, bạn nào ở đây muốn bảo vệ phân tích lợi - ích chi phí Từ ví dụ phản đề rõ ràng này, có ai muốn biện hộ không? hay bạn nghĩ nó đã hoàn toàn phá hủy phép tính tính vị lợi? Vâng. Tôi nghĩ rằng, một lần nữa họ lại mắc cùng một sai lầm như ở ví dụ trước khi họ đã gán một giá trị bằng tiền cho sinh mạng con người và một lần nữa họ không tính đến những thứ như đau khổ và mất mát về tình cảm gia đình. Ý tôi là những gia đình đã bị mất đi nguồn sống nhưng họ cũng mất đi người thân và điều đó còn đáng giá hơn 200 nghìn đô la. Tốt, nhưng chờ đã nào, bạn tên gì? Julie Roto. Vậy nếu là 200 nghìn đô la, Julie, Là một con số quá thấp vì chưa bao gồm sự mất mát của một người thân, và sự mất mát của những năm tháng cuộc đời, Vậy bạn nghĩ con số nào, bạn nghĩ con số bao nhiêu sẽ chính xác hơn? Tôi không tin là mình có thể đưa ra một con số. Tôi nghĩ rằng kiểu phân tích này không nên áp dụng cho những vấn đề về sinh mạng con người. Tôi nghĩ rằng không thể dung tiền đối với vấn đề này. Vậy họ không chỉ đưa ra một con số quá thấp Julie nói rằng, họ đã sai khi cố gắng áp đặt bất kỳ một con số nào. được rồi, hãy nghe một ý kiến khác. Ai nào? Phải tính thêm cả điều chỉnh do lạm phát nữa được rồi, thế là công bằng. Vậy bây giờ con số sẽ là bao nhiêu? Đấy là 35 năm trước Hai triệu đô la. Bạn đưa ra con số hai triệu đô la. Và bạn tên gì? Voicheck Voicheck nói rằng chúng ta phải tính thêm cả lạm phát, chúng ta nên hào phóng hơn Nếu vậy các bạn có hài lòng xem đây là cách nghĩ đúng cho câu hỏi này không? Thật không may, tôi đoán là. Cần phải đặt ra một con số ở đâu đó Tôi không chắc sẽ là số nào nhưng tôi đồng ý rằng có thể gán cho mạng người một con số. Được rồi, như vậy Voicheck nói, và ở đây cậu ấy không đồng ý với Julie Julie nói rằng chúng ta không thể gán cho mạng người một con số, để phân tích lợi ích - chi phí, Voicheck nói rằng chúng ta phải làm như vậy bởi vì bằng cách này hay cách khác, chúng ta phải quyết định những bạn khác nghĩ sao về điều này? Có ai sẵn sàng để biện hộ rằng phân tích lợi ích - chi phí ở đây Là chính xác và thỏa đáng không? Tôi nghĩ rằng, nếu Ford và các công ty xe hơi khác không sử dụng phân tích lợi ích - chi phí thì cuối cùng họ sẽ bị phá sản vì họ sẽ chẳng thể có lợi nhuận và hàng triệu người sẽ không có ô tô của hãng này để đi làm, để có thức ăn trên bàn để nuôi con cái của họ, vì vậy tôi nghĩ rằng nếu phân tích lợi ích - chi phí không được sử dụng, thì một lợi ích lớn hơn sẽ mất đi trong trường hợp đó. Được rồi, cho tôi hỏi, bạn tên gì? Raul. Raul. Gần đây đã có một nghiên cứu được thực hiện về việc sử dụng điện thoại di động của tài xế khi đang lái một chiếc ô tô, và có một cuộc tranh luận liệu việc đó có nên bị cấm hay không và con số là, khoảng hai nghìn người chết vì tai nạn mỗi năm, khi sử dụng điện thoại di động Và phân tích lợi ích - chi phí được thực hiện bởi trung tâm phân tích rủi ro ở Harvard found that if you look at the benefits of the cell phone use and you put some value on the life, it comes out about the same because of the enormous economic benefit of enabling people to take advantage of their time, not waste time, be able to make deals and talk to friends and so on while they're driving doesn't that suggest that it's a mistake to try to put monetary figures on questions of human life? well I think that if the great majority of people tried to derive maximum utility out of a service like using cell phones and the convenience that cell phones provide that sacrifice is necessary for satisfaction to occur. You're an outright utilitarian. In, yes okay. all right then, one last question Raul and I put this to Voicheck, what dollar figure should be put on human life to decide whether to ban the use of cell phones well I don't want to arbitrarily calculate a figure, I mean right now I think that you want to take it under advisement. yeah I'll take it under advisement. but what roughly speaking would it be? you've got 23 hundred deaths you've got to assign a dollar value to know whether you want to prevent those deaths by banning the use of cell phones in cars so what would you're hunch be? how much? million two million two million was Voitech's figure is that about right? maybe a million. a million.?! Alright that's good, thank you So these are some of the controversies that arise these days from cost-benefit analysis especially those that involve placing a dollar value on everything to be added up. well now I want to turn to your objections, to your objections not necessarily to cost benefit analysis specifically, because that's just one version of the utilitarian logic in practice today, but to the theory as a whole, to the idea that the right thing to do, the just basis for policy and law, is to maximize utility. How many disagree with the utilitarian approach to law and to the common good? How many bring with it? so more agree than disagree. so let's hear from the critics my main issue with it is that I feel like you can't say that just because someone's in the minority what they want and need is less valuable than someone who's in the majority so I guess I have an issue with the idea that the greatest good for the greatest number is okay because there is still what about people who are in the lesser number, like it's not fair to them they didn't have a say in where they wanted to be. alright now that's an interesting objection, you're worried about the effect on minority. yes. what's your name by the way. Anna. alright who has an answer to Anna's worry about the effect on the minority What do you say to Anna? she said that the minorities value less, I don't think that's the case because individually the minorities value is just the same as the individual in the majority it's just that the numbers outweigh the minority and I mean at a certain point you have to make a decision and I'm sorry for the minority but sometimes it's for the general for the greater good. For the greater good, Anna what do you say? what's your name? Youngda. What do you say to Youngda? Youngda says you just have to add up people's preferences and those in the minority do have their preferences weighed. can you give an example of the kind of thing you're worried about when you say you're worried about utilitarianism violating the concern or respect due the minority? can you give an example. so well with any of the cases that we've talked about, like with the shipwreck one, I think that the boy who was eaten still had just as much of a right to live as the other people and just because he was the minority in that case the one who maybe had less of a chance to keep living that doesn't mean that the others automatically have a right to eat him just because it would give a greater amount of people the chance to live. so there may be a certain rights that the minority members have that the individual has that shouldn't be traded off for the sake of utility? yes Anna? Now this would be a test for you, back in ancient Rome they threw Christians to the lions in the coliseum for sport if you think how the utilitarian calculus would go yes, the Christian thrown to the lion suffers enormous excruciating pain, but look at the collective ecstasy of the Romans. Youngda. Well in that time I don't think in the modern-day of time to value the, um, to given a number to the happiness given to the people watching I don't think any policy maker would say the pain of one person, the suffering of one person is much much, in comparison to the happiness gained no but you have to admit that if there were enough Romans delirious with happiness, it would outweigh even the most excruciating pain of a handful of Christians thrown to the lion. so we really have here two different objections to utilitarianism one has to do with whether utilitarianism adequately respects individual rights or minority rights and the other has to do with the whole idea of aggregating utility for preferences or values is it possible to aggregate all values to translate them into dollar terms? there was in the 1930's a psychologist who tried to address the second question. He tried to prove what utilitarianism assumes, that it is possible to translate all goods, all values, all human concerns into a single uniform measure and he did this by conducting a survey of the young recipients of relief, this was in the 1930's and he asked them, he gave them a list of unpleasant experiences and he asked them how much would you have to be paid to undergo the following experiences and he kept track for example how much would you have to be paid to have one upper front tooth pulled out or how much would you have to be paid to have one little one tow cut off? or eat a live earth worm, six inches long or to live the rest of your life on a farm in Kansas or to choke a stray cat to death with your bare hands now what do you suppose what do you suppose was the most expensive item on that list Kansas? You're right it was Kansas for a Kansas people said they'd have to pay them they have to be paid three hundred thousand dollars what do you think what do you think was the next most expensive? not the cat not the tooth not the toe the worm! people said you'd have to pay them a hundred thousand dollars to eat the worm what do you think was the least expensive item? not the cat the tooth during the depression people were willing to have their tooth pulled for only forty five hundred dollars now here's what Thorndike concluded from his study any want or satisfaction which exists, exists in some amount and is therefore measurable the life of a dog or a cat or a chicken consists of appetites cravings desires and their gratifications so does the life of human beings though the appetites and desires are more complicated but what about Thorndike's study? does it support Bentham's idea that all goods all values can be captured according to a single uniform measure of value or does the preposterous character of those different items on the list suggest the opposite conclusion that may be whether we're talking about life or Kansas or the worm maybe the things we value and cherish can't be captured according to a single uniform measure of value and if they can't what are the consequences for the utilitarian theory of morality that's a question we'll continue with next time alright now let's take the other part of the poll which is the the highest experience or pleasure? how many say Shakespeare how many say fear Factor no you can't be serious really? last time last time we began to consider some objections to Jeremy Bentham's version of utilitarianism people raised two objections in the discussion we had the first was the objection, the claim that utilitarianism, by concerning itself with the greatest good for the greatest number fails adequately to respect individual rights. today we have debates about torture and terrorism suppose a suspected terrorists was apprehended on September tenth and you had reason to believe that the suspect had crucial information about an impending terrorist attack that would kill over three thousand people and you couldn't extract the information would it be just to torture the suspect to get the information or do you say no there is a categorical moral duty of respect for individual rights in a way we're back to the questions we started with t about trolley cars and organ transplants so that's the first issue and you remember we considered some examples of cost-benefit analysis but a lot of people were unhappy with cost-benefit analysis when it came to placing a dollar value on human life and so that led us to the second objection, it questioned whether it's possible to translate all values into a single uniform measure of value it asks in other words whether all values are commensurable let me give you one other example of an experience, this actually is a true story, it comes from personal experience that raises a question at least about whether all values can be translated without loss into utilitarian terms some years ago when I was a graduate student I was at Oxford in England and they had menâs and women's colleges they weren't yet mixed and the women's colleges had rules against overnight male guests by the nineteen seventies these rules were rarely enforced and easily violated, or so I was told, by the late nineteen seventies when I was there, pressure grew to relax these rules and it became the subject of debate among the faculty at St. Anne's College which was one of these all women colleges the older women on the faculty we're traditionalists they were opposed to change on conventional moral grounds but times had changed and they were embarrassed to give the true grounds of their objection and so the translated their arguments into utilitarian terms if men stay overnight, they argued, the costs to the college will increase. how you might wonder well they'll want to take baths, and that will use up hot water they said furthermore they argued we'll have to replace the mattresses more often the reformers met these arguments by adopting the following compromise each woman could have a maximum of three overnight male guest each week they didn't say whether it had to be the same one, or three different provided and this is the compromise provided the guest paid fifty pence to defray the cost to the college the next day the national headline in the national newspaper read St. Anne's girls, fifty pence a night another illustration of the difficulty of translating all values in this case a certain idea of virtue into utilitarian terms so that's all to illustrate the second objection to utilitarianism, at least the part of that objection that questions rather the utilitarianism is right to assume that we can assume the uniformity of value, the commensurability of values and translate all moral considerations into dollars or money. But there is a second aspect to this worry about aggregating values and preferences why should we weigh all preferences that people have without assessing whether they're good preferences or bad preferences shouldn't we distinguish between higher pleasures and lower pleasures. Now, part of the appeal of not making any qualitative distinctions about the worth of people's preferences, part of the appeal is that it is non-judgmental and egalitarian the Benthamite utilitarian says everybody's preferences count and they count regardless of what people want regardless of what makes it different people happy. For Bentham, all that matters you'll remember are the intensity and the duration of a pleasure or pain the so-called higher pleasures or nobler virtues are simply those, according to Bentham that produce stronger, longer, pleasure yet a famous phrase to express this idea the quantity of pleasure being equal pushpin is as good as poetry. What was pushpin? It was some kind of a child's game like to tidily winks pushpin is as good as poetry Bentham said and lying behind this idea I think is the claim the intuition that it's a presumption to judge whose pleasures are intrinsically higher or worthier or better and there is something attractive in this refusal to judge, after all some people like Mozart, others Madonna some people like ballet others bowling, who's to say a Benthamite might argue, who's to say which of these pleasures whose pleasures are higher worthier nobler than others? But, is that right? this refusal to make qualitative distinctions can we altogether dispense with the idea that certain things we take pleasure in are better or worthier than others think back to the case of the Romans in the coliseum, one thing that troubled people about that practice is that it seemed to violate the rights of the Christian another way of objecting to what's going on there is that the pleasure that the Romans take in this bloody spectacle should that pleasure which is a base, kind of corrupt degrading pleasure, should that even be valorized or weighed in deciding what the the general welfare is? so here are the objections to Bentham's utilitarianism and now we turn to someone who tried to respond to those objections, a later day utilitarian John Stuart Mill so what we need to examine now is whether John Stuart Mill had a convincing reply to these objections to utilitarianism. John Stuart Mill was born in 1806 his father James Mill was a disciple of Benthamâs and James Mills set about giving his son John Stuart Mill a model education he was a child prodigy John Stuart Mill the knew Latin, sorry, Greek at the age of three, Latin at eight and at age ten he wrote a history of Roman law. At age twenty he had a nervous breakdown this left him in a depression for five years but at age twenty five what helped lift him out of this depression is that he met Harriet Taylor she in no doubt married him, they lived happily ever after and it was under her influence the John Stuart Mill try to humanize utilitarianism what Mill tried to do was to see whether the utilitarian calculus could be enlarged and modified to accommodate humanitarian concerns like the concern to respect individual rights and also to address the distinction between higher and lower pleasures. In 1859 Mill wrote a famous book on liberty the main point of which was the importance of defending individual rights and minority rights and in 1861 toward the end of his life he wrote the book we read is part of this course Utilitarianism. It makes it clear that utility is the only standard of morality in his view so he's not challenging Bentham's premise, he's affirming it. he says very explicitly the sole evidence, it is possible to produce that anything is desirable is that people actually do desire it. so he stays with the idea that our de facto actual empirical desires are the only basis for moral judgment. but then page eight also in chapter two, he argues that it is possible for a utilitarian to distinguish higher from lower pleasures. now, those of you who've read Mill already how according to him is it possible to draw that distinction? How can a utilitarian distinguish qualitatively higher pleasures from lesser ones, base ones, unworthy ones? If you tried both of them and you'll prefer the higher one naturally always that's great, that's right. What's your name? John. so as John points out Mill says here's the test, since we can't step outside actual desires, actual preferences that would violate utilitarian premises, the only test of whether a pleasure is higher or lower is whether someone who has experienced both would prefer it. And here, in chapter two we see the passage where Mill makes the point that John just described of two pleasures, if there be one to which all are almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, in other words no outside, no independent standard, then that is the more desirable pleasure. what do people think about that argument. does that does it succeeded? how many think that it does succeed? of arguing within utilitarian terms for a distinction between higher and lower pleasures. how many think it doesn't succeed? I want to hear your reasons. but before we give the reasons let's do an experiment of Mills' claim. In order to do this experiment we're going to look that three short excerpts of popular entertainment the first one is a Hamlet soliloquy it'll be followed by two other experiences see what you think. 'what a piece of work is a man how noble in reason how infinite in faculties in form and moving, how express and admirable in action how like an angel. In apprehension, how like a god the beauty of the world the paragon of animals and yet, to me what is this quintessence of dust? man delights not me. Imagine a world where your greatest fears become reality each show, six contestants from around the country battle each other in three extreme stunts. these stunts are designed to challenge these contestants both physically and mentally six contestants, three stunts, one winner. Fear factor. The Simpsons. Well hi diddly-o peddle to the metal o-philes! Flanders- since when do you like anything cool. well, I don't care for the speed, but I can't get enough of that safety gear helmets, roll bars, caution flags. I like the fresh air and looking at the poor people in the infield. Dang Cletus, why you got to park by my parents. Now hunny, it's my parents too. I don't even have to ask which one you like most the Simpsons? How many like the Simpson's most? How many Shakespeare? What about fear factor? how many preferred fear factor? really? people overwhelmingly like the Simpsons better than Shakespeare. alright, now let's take the other part of the poll which is the highest experience or pleasure? how many say Shakespeare? how many say fear factor? no you can't be serious really? alright go ahead you can say it. I found that one the most entertaining I know but which do you think was the worthiest, the noblest experience, I know you find it the most anything if something is good just because it is pleasurable what is the matter if you have some kind of abstract idea of whether it is good by someone else's sense or not. Alright so you come down on the straight Benthamite's side whose to judge and why should we judge apart from just registering and aggregating de facto preferences, alright fair enough. what's your name? Nate? okay fair enough Alright so how many think that the Simpson's is actually apart from liking is actually the higher experience higher than Shakespeare. Alright let's see the vote for Shakespeare again how many think Shakespeare is higher? alright so why is it ideally I'd like to hear from someone is there someone think Shakespeare is highest but who preferred watching the Simpsons Like I guess just sitting and watching the Simpsons, it's entertaining because the make jokes, they make us laugh but someone has to tell us that Shakespeare was this great writer we had to be taught how to read him, how to understand him, we had to be taught how to take in Rembrandt, how to analyze a painting. well how do, what's your name? Aneesha. Aneesha, when you say someone told you that Shakespeare's better are you accepting it on blind faith you voted that Shakespeare's higher only because the culture tells you that our teachers tell you that or do you actually agree with that yourself well in the sense that Shakespeare, no, but earlier you made an example of Rembrandt I feel like I would enjoy a reading a comic book more than I would enjoy a kind of analyzing Rembrandt because someone told me it was great, you know. Right so of some this seems to be, you're suggesting a kind of cultural convention and pressure. We're told what books, what works of art are great. who else? although I enjoyed watching the Simpsons more in this particular moment in Justice, if I were to spend the rest of my life considering the three different video clips shown I would not want to spend that remainder of my life considering the latter two clips. I think I would derive more pleasure from being able to branch out in my own mind sort of considering more deep pleasures, more deep thoughts. and tell me your name Joe. Joe, so if you had to spend the rest of your life on on a farm in Kansas with only with only Shakespeare or the collected episodes of the Simpsons you would prefer Shakespeare what do you conclude from that about John Stuart Mill's test but the test of a higher pleasure is whether people who have experienced both prefer it. can I cite another example briefly? in biology in neuro biology last year we were told of a rat who was tested a particular center in the brain where the rat was able to stimulate its brain and cause itself intense pleasure repeatedly the rat did not eat or drink until it died so the rat was clearly experiencing intense pleasure now if you asked me right now if I'd rather experience intense pleasure or have a full lifetime of higher pleasure, I would consider intense pleasure to be lower pleasure, right now enjoy intense pleasure yes I would but over a lifetime I think I would think almost a complete majority here would agree that they would rather be a human with higher pleasure that rat with intense pleasure for a momentary period of time so now in answer to your question, right, I think this proves that, or I won't say proves I think the conclusion is that Mill's theory that when a majority people are asked what they would rather do, they will answer that they would rather engage in a higher pleasure. So you think that this supports Mills, that Mills was on to something here I do. all right is there anyone who disagrees with Joe who thinks that our experiment disproves Mills' test shows that that's not an adequate way that you can't distinguish higher pleasures within the utilitarian framework. If whatever is good is truly just whatever people prefer it's truly relative and there's no objective definition then there will be some society where people prefer Simpsons more anyone can appreciate the Simpsons, but I think it does take education to appreciate Shakespeare Alright, you're saying it takes education to appreciate higher true thing Mill's point is that the higher pleasures do require cultivation and appreciation and education he doesn't dispute that but once having been cultivated and educated people will see not only see the difference between higher lower pleasures but will it actually prefer the higher to the lower. you find this famous passage from John Stuart Mill- it is better to be a human being dissatisfied then a pig satisfied. Better to the Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied and if the fool or the pig are of a different opinion it is because they only know their side of the question. so here you have an attempt to distinguish higher from lower pleasures so going to an art museum or being a couch potato, swilling beer watching television at home sometimes Mill agrees we might succumb to the temptation to do the latter, to be couch potatoes, but even when we do that out of indolence and sloth, we know that the pleasure we get gazing at Rembrandts in the museum is actually higher, because we've experienced both. And is a higher pressure gazing at Rembrandts because of engages our higher human faculties what about Mill's attempt to reply to the objection about individual rights? In a way he uses the same kind of argument and this comes out in chapter five he says while I dispute the pretensions of any theory which sets up an imaginary standard of justice not grounded on utility, but still he considers justice grounded on utility to be what he calls the chief part and incomparably the most sacred and binding part of all morality. so justice is higher individual rights are privileged but not for reasons that depart from utilitarian assumptions. Justice is a name for certain moral requirements which, regarded collectively stand higher in the scale of social utility and are therefore of more paramount obligation than any others so justice is sacred, it's prior, it's privileged, it isn't something that can easily be traded off against lesser things but the reason is ultimately Mills Claims a utilitarian reason once you consider the long run interests of humankind, of all of us, as progressive beings. If we do justice and if we respect rights society as a whole will be better off in the long run. Well is that convincing? Or is Mill actually, without admitting it, stepping outside utilitarian considerations in arguing for qualitatively higher pleasures and for sacred or specially important individual rights? we haven't fully answered that question because to answer that question in the case of rights and justice will require that we explore other ways, non utilitarian ways of accounting for the basis or rights and then asking whether they succeed as for Jeremy Bentham, who launched utilitarianism as a doctrine in moral and legal philosophy Bentham died in 1832 at the age of eighty five but if you go to London you can visit him today literally. he provided in his will that his body be preserved, embalmed and displayed in the university of London where he still presides in a glass case with a wax head dressed in his actual clothing. you see before he died, Bentham addressed himself to a question consistent with his philosophy, of what use could a dead man be to the living one use, he said, would be to make one's corpse available for the study of anatomy in the case of great philosophers, however, better yet to preserve one's physical presence in order to inspire future generations of thinkers. You want to see what Bentham looks like stuffed? Here's what he looks like There he is now, if you look closely you'll notice that the embalming up his actual had was not a success so they substituted a waxed head and at the bottom for verisimilitude you can actually see his actual had on a plate you see it? right there so, what's the moral of the story? the moral of the story by the way they bring him out during meetings of the board at university college London and the minutes record him as present but not voting. here is a philosopher in life and in death who adhered to the principles of his philosophy. we'll continue with rights next time. Don't miss the chance to interact online with other viewers of Justice join the conversation, take a pop quiz, watch lectures you've missed, and a lot more. Visit Justiceharvard.org It's the right thing to do. funding for this program is provided by additional funding provided by