WEBVTT 00:00:06.545 --> 00:00:08.985 In a study in the 1990s, 00:00:08.985 --> 00:00:13.887 participants recalled getting lost in a shopping mall as children. 00:00:13.887 --> 00:00:17.207 Some shared these memories in vivid detail— 00:00:17.207 --> 00:00:20.887 one even remembered that the old man who rescued him 00:00:20.887 --> 00:00:23.863 was wearing a flannel shirt. NOTE Paragraph 00:00:23.863 --> 00:00:28.148 But none of these people had actually gotten lost in a mall. 00:00:28.148 --> 00:00:30.378 They produced these false memories 00:00:30.378 --> 00:00:35.096 when the psychologists conducting the study told them they’d gotten lost, 00:00:35.096 --> 00:00:37.696 and although they might not remember the incident, 00:00:37.696 --> 00:00:40.456 their parents had confirmed it. 00:00:40.456 --> 00:00:45.311 And it wasn’t just one or two people who thought they remembered getting lost— 00:00:45.311 --> 00:00:48.161 a quarter of the participants did. NOTE Paragraph 00:00:48.161 --> 00:00:50.921 These findings may sound unbelievable, 00:00:50.921 --> 00:00:54.571 but they actually reflect a very common experience. 00:00:54.571 --> 00:00:57.821 Our memories are sometimes unreliable. 00:00:57.821 --> 00:01:01.821 And though we still don’t know precisely what causes this fallibility 00:01:01.821 --> 00:01:03.591 on a neurological level, 00:01:03.591 --> 00:01:07.591 research has highlighted some of the most common ways our memories 00:01:07.591 --> 00:01:10.591 diverge from what actually happened. NOTE Paragraph 00:01:10.591 --> 00:01:14.431 The mall study highlights how we can incorporate information 00:01:14.431 --> 00:01:16.161 from outside sources, 00:01:16.161 --> 00:01:18.391 like other people or the news, 00:01:18.391 --> 00:01:22.566 into our personal recollections without realizing it. 00:01:22.566 --> 00:01:27.129 This kind of suggestibility is just one influence on our memories. 00:01:27.129 --> 00:01:28.249 Take another study, 00:01:28.249 --> 00:01:32.574 in which researchers briefly showed a random collection of photographs 00:01:32.574 --> 00:01:34.174 to a group of participants, 00:01:34.174 --> 00:01:39.817 including images of a university campus none of them had ever visited. 00:01:39.817 --> 00:01:42.367 When shown the images three weeks later, 00:01:42.367 --> 00:01:47.246 a majority of participants said that they had probably or definitely 00:01:47.246 --> 00:01:50.076 visited the campus in the past. NOTE Paragraph 00:01:50.076 --> 00:01:55.669 The participants misattributed information from one context— an image they’d seen— 00:01:55.669 --> 00:02:01.067 onto another— a memory of something they believed they actually experienced. 00:02:01.067 --> 00:02:05.545 In another experiment, people were shown an image of a magnifying glass, 00:02:05.545 --> 00:02:09.065 and then told to imagine a lollipop. 00:02:09.065 --> 00:02:13.994 They frequently recalled that they saw the magnifying glass and the lollipop. 00:02:13.994 --> 00:02:17.464 They struggled to link the objects to the correct context— 00:02:17.464 --> 00:02:21.464 whether they actually saw them, or simply imagined them. NOTE Paragraph 00:02:21.464 --> 00:02:25.464 Another study, where a psychologist questioned over 2,000 people 00:02:25.464 --> 00:02:29.044 on their views about the legalization of marijuana, 00:02:29.044 --> 00:02:32.494 highlights yet another kind of influence on memory. 00:02:32.494 --> 00:02:38.462 Participants answered questions in 1973 and 1982. 00:02:38.462 --> 00:02:43.361 Those who said they had supported marijuana legalization in 1973, 00:02:43.361 --> 00:02:46.841 but reported they were against it in 1982, 00:02:46.841 --> 00:02:53.402 were more likely to recall that they were actually against legalization in 1973— 00:02:53.402 --> 00:02:57.790 bringing their old views in line with their current ones. 00:02:57.790 --> 00:03:00.920 Our current opinions, feelings, and experiences 00:03:00.920 --> 00:03:04.920 can bias our memories of how we felt in the past. 00:03:04.920 --> 00:03:06.060 In another study, 00:03:06.060 --> 00:03:10.262 researchers gave two groups of participants background information 00:03:10.262 --> 00:03:16.672 on a historical war and asked them to rate the likelihood that each side would win. 00:03:16.672 --> 00:03:19.232 They gave each group the same information, 00:03:19.232 --> 00:03:23.539 except that they only told one group who had actually won the war— 00:03:23.539 --> 00:03:27.139 the other group didn’t know the real world outcome. 00:03:27.139 --> 00:03:30.549 In theory, both groups’ answers should be similar, 00:03:30.549 --> 00:03:32.839 because the likelihood of each side winning 00:03:32.839 --> 00:03:35.519 isn’t effected by who actually won— 00:03:35.519 --> 00:03:39.879 if there’s a 20% chance of thunderstorms, and a thunderstorm happens, 00:03:39.879 --> 00:03:44.976 the chance of thunderstorms doesn’t retroactively go up to 100%. 00:03:44.976 --> 00:03:48.366 Still, the group that knew how the war ended 00:03:48.366 --> 00:03:53.956 rated the winning side as more likely to win than the group who did not. NOTE Paragraph 00:03:53.956 --> 00:03:58.195 All of these fallibilities of memory can have real-world impacts. 00:03:58.195 --> 00:04:03.502 If police interrogations use leading questions with eye witnesses or suspects, 00:04:03.502 --> 00:04:10.813 suggestibility could result in incorrect identifications or unreliable confessions. 00:04:10.813 --> 00:04:13.393 Even in the absence of leading questions, 00:04:13.393 --> 00:04:17.775 misattribution can lead to inaccurate eyewitness testimony. 00:04:17.775 --> 00:04:18.655 In a courtroom, 00:04:18.655 --> 00:04:21.685 if a judge rules a piece of evidence inadmissible 00:04:21.685 --> 00:04:26.263 and tells jurors to disregard it, they may not be able to do so. 00:04:26.263 --> 00:04:29.773 In a medical setting, if a patient seeks a second opinion 00:04:29.773 --> 00:04:33.773 and the second physician is aware of the first one’s diagnosis, 00:04:33.773 --> 00:04:37.403 that knowledge may bias their conclusion. 00:04:37.403 --> 00:04:41.403 Our memories are not ironclad representations of reality, 00:04:41.403 --> 00:04:43.753 but subjective perceptions. 00:04:43.753 --> 00:04:46.653 And there’s not necessarily anything wrong with that— 00:04:46.653 --> 00:04:50.653 the problems arise when we treat memory as fact, 00:04:50.653 --> 00:04:53.023 rather than accepting this fundamental truth 00:04:53.023 --> 00:04:56.063 about the nature of our recollections.