WEBVTT 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In a study in the 1990s, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 participants recalled getting lost in a shopping mall as children. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Some shared these memories in vivid detail— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 one even remembered that the old man 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 who rescued him was wearing a flannel shirt. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 But none of these people had actually gotten lost in a mall. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They produced these false memories 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 when the psychologists conducting the study told them they’d gotten lost, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and although they might not remember the incident, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 their parents had confirmed it. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 And it wasn’t just one or two people who thought they remembered getting lost— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 a quarter of the participants did. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 These findings may sound unbelievable, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but they actually reflect a very common experience. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Our memories are sometimes unreliable. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 And though we still don’t know precisely what causes this fallibility 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 on a neurological level, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 research has highlighted some of the most common ways our memories 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 diverge from what actually happened. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 The mall study highlights how we can incorporate information 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 from outside sources, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 like other people or the news, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 into our personal recollections without realizing it. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 This kind of suggestibility is just one influence on our memories. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Take another study, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 in which researchers briefly showed a random collection of photographs 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 to a group of participants, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 including images of a university campus none of them had ever visited. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 When shown the images three weeks later, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 a majority of participants said that they had probably or definitely 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 visited the campus in the past. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 The participants misattributed information from one context––an image they’d seen— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 onto another––a memory of something they believed they actually experienced. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In another experiment, people were shown an image of a magnifying glass, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and then told to imagine a lollipop. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They frequently recalled that they saw the magnifying glass and the lollipop. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They struggled to link the objects to the correct context–– 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 whether they actually saw them, or simply imagined them. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Another study, where a psychologist questioned over 2,000 people 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 on their views about the legalization of marijuana, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 highlights yet another kind of influence on memory. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Participants answered questions in 1973 and 1982. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Those who said they had supported marijuana legalization in 1973, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but reported they were against it in 1982, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 were more likely to recall that they were actually against legalization in 1973–– 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 bringing their old views in line with their current ones. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Our current opinions, feelings, and experiences can bias our memories of how we felt in the past. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In another study, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 researchers gave two groups of participants background information 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 on a historical war and asked them to rate the likelihood that each side would win. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 They gave each group the same information, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 except that they only told one group who had actually won the war— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the other group didn’t know the real world outcome. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In theory, both groups’ answers should be similar, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 because the likelihood of each side winning 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 isn’t effected by who actually won— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 if there’s a 20% chance of thunderstorms, and a thunderstorm happens, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the chance of thunderstorms doesn’t retroactively go up to 100%. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Still, the group that knew how the war ended rated the winning side 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 as more likely to win than the group who did not. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 All of these fallibilities of memory can have real-world impacts. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 If police interrogations use leading questions with eye witnesses or suspects, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 suggestibility could result in incorrect identifications or unreliable confessions. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Even in the absence of leading questions, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 misattribution can lead to inaccurate eyewitness testimony. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In a courtroom, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 if a judge rules a piece of evidence inadmissible 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and tells jurors to disregard it, they may not be able to do so. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 In a medical setting, if a patient seeks a second opinions 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 and the second physician is aware of the first one’s diagnosis, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 that knowledge may bias their conclusion. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 Our memories are not ironclad representations of reality, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 but subjective perceptions. 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 And there’s not necessarily anything wrong with that— 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 the problems arise when we treat memory as fact, 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 rather than accepting this fundamental truth 99:59:59.999 --> 99:59:59.999 about the nature of our recollections.