1 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In a study in the 1990s, 2 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 participants recalled getting lost in a shopping mall as children. 3 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Some shared these memories in vivid detail— 4 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 one even remembered that the old man 5 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 who rescued him was wearing a flannel shirt. 6 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 But none of these people had actually gotten lost in a mall. 7 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They produced these false memories 8 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 when the psychologists conducting the study told them they’d gotten lost, 9 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and although they might not remember the incident, 10 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 their parents had confirmed it. 11 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And it wasn’t just one or two people who thought they remembered getting lost— 12 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a quarter of the participants did. 13 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 These findings may sound unbelievable, 14 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but they actually reflect a very common experience. 15 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Our memories are sometimes unreliable. 16 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And though we still don’t know precisely what causes this fallibility 17 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on a neurological level, 18 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 research has highlighted some of the most common ways our memories 19 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 diverge from what actually happened. 20 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The mall study highlights how we can incorporate information 21 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 from outside sources, 22 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 like other people or the news, 23 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 into our personal recollections without realizing it. 24 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 This kind of suggestibility is just one influence on our memories. 25 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Take another study, 26 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 in which researchers briefly showed a random collection of photographs 27 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 to a group of participants, 28 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 including images of a university campus none of them had ever visited. 29 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 When shown the images three weeks later, 30 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 a majority of participants said that they had probably or definitely 31 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 visited the campus in the past. 32 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 The participants misattributed information from one context––an image they’d seen— 33 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 onto another––a memory of something they believed they actually experienced. 34 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In another experiment, people were shown an image of a magnifying glass, 35 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and then told to imagine a lollipop. 36 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They frequently recalled that they saw the magnifying glass and the lollipop. 37 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They struggled to link the objects to the correct context–– 38 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 whether they actually saw them, or simply imagined them. 39 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Another study, where a psychologist questioned over 2,000 people 40 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on their views about the legalization of marijuana, 41 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 highlights yet another kind of influence on memory. 42 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Participants answered questions in 1973 and 1982. 43 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Those who said they had supported marijuana legalization in 1973, 44 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but reported they were against it in 1982, 45 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 were more likely to recall that they were actually against legalization in 1973–– 46 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 bringing their old views in line with their current ones. 47 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Our current opinions, feelings, and experiences can bias our memories of how we felt in the past. 48 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In another study, 49 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 researchers gave two groups of participants background information 50 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 on a historical war and asked them to rate the likelihood that each side would win. 51 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 They gave each group the same information, 52 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 except that they only told one group who had actually won the war— 53 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the other group didn’t know the real world outcome. 54 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In theory, both groups’ answers should be similar, 55 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 because the likelihood of each side winning 56 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 isn’t effected by who actually won— 57 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if there’s a 20% chance of thunderstorms, and a thunderstorm happens, 58 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the chance of thunderstorms doesn’t retroactively go up to 100%. 59 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Still, the group that knew how the war ended rated the winning side 60 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 as more likely to win than the group who did not. 61 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 All of these fallibilities of memory can have real-world impacts. 62 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 If police interrogations use leading questions with eye witnesses or suspects, 63 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 suggestibility could result in incorrect identifications or unreliable confessions. 64 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Even in the absence of leading questions, 65 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 misattribution can lead to inaccurate eyewitness testimony. 66 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In a courtroom, 67 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 if a judge rules a piece of evidence inadmissible 68 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and tells jurors to disregard it, they may not be able to do so. 69 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 In a medical setting, if a patient seeks a second opinions 70 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 and the second physician is aware of the first one’s diagnosis, 71 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 that knowledge may bias their conclusion. 72 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 Our memories are not ironclad representations of reality, 73 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 but subjective perceptions. 74 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 And there’s not necessarily anything wrong with that— 75 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 the problems arise when we treat memory as fact, 76 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 rather than accepting this fundamental truth 77 99:59:59,999 --> 99:59:59,999 about the nature of our recollections.