1 00:00:06,657 --> 00:00:09,077 Here are two images of a house. 2 00:00:09,077 --> 00:00:11,347 There’s one obvious difference, 3 00:00:11,347 --> 00:00:13,807 but to this patient, P.S., 4 00:00:13,807 --> 00:00:16,607 they looked completely identical. 5 00:00:16,607 --> 00:00:20,367 P.S. had suffered a stroke that damaged the right side of her brain, 6 00:00:20,367 --> 00:00:24,017 leaving her unaware of everything on her left side. 7 00:00:24,017 --> 00:00:27,557 But though she could discern no difference between the houses, 8 00:00:27,557 --> 00:00:30,947 when researchers asked her which she would prefer to live in, 9 00:00:30,947 --> 00:00:33,787 she chose the house that wasn’t burning— 10 00:00:33,787 --> 00:00:36,897 not once, but again and again. 11 00:00:36,897 --> 00:00:40,317 P.S.’s brain was still processing information 12 00:00:40,317 --> 00:00:42,437 from her whole field of vision. 13 00:00:42,437 --> 00:00:44,097 She could see both images 14 00:00:44,097 --> 00:00:46,077 and tell the difference between them, 15 00:00:46,077 --> 00:00:47,837 she just didn’t know it. 16 00:00:47,837 --> 00:00:50,547 If someone threw a ball at her left side, 17 00:00:50,547 --> 00:00:51,527 she might duck. 18 00:00:51,527 --> 00:00:54,777 But she wouldn’t have any awareness of the ball, 19 00:00:54,777 --> 00:00:57,457 or any idea why she ducked. 20 00:00:57,457 --> 00:00:58,877 P.S.’s condition, 21 00:00:58,877 --> 00:01:01,147 known as hemispatial neglect, 22 00:01:01,147 --> 00:01:05,987 reveals an important distinction between the brain’s processing of information 23 00:01:05,987 --> 00:01:09,164 and our experience of that processing. 24 00:01:09,164 --> 00:01:13,034 That experience is what we call consciousness. 25 00:01:13,034 --> 00:01:18,044 We are conscious of both the external world and our internal selves— 26 00:01:18,044 --> 00:01:19,815 we are aware of an image 27 00:01:19,815 --> 00:01:23,685 in much the same way we are aware of ourselves looking at an image, 28 00:01:23,685 --> 00:01:26,455 or our inner thoughts and emotions. 29 00:01:26,455 --> 00:01:28,965 But where does consciousness come from? 30 00:01:28,965 --> 00:01:31,815 Scientists, theologians, and philosophers 31 00:01:31,815 --> 00:01:35,625 have been trying to get to the bottom of this question for centuries— 32 00:01:35,625 --> 00:01:38,225 without reaching any consensus. 33 00:01:38,225 --> 00:01:39,935 One recent theory is that 34 00:01:39,935 --> 00:01:44,865 consciousness is the brain’s imperfect picture of its own activity. 35 00:01:44,865 --> 00:01:46,335 To understand this theory, 36 00:01:46,335 --> 00:01:47,965 it helps to have a clear idea 37 00:01:47,965 --> 00:01:52,795 of one important way the brain processes information from our senses. 38 00:01:52,795 --> 00:01:54,404 Based on sensory input, 39 00:01:54,404 --> 00:01:55,764 it builds models, 40 00:01:55,764 --> 00:01:59,164 which are continuously updating, simplified descriptions 41 00:01:59,164 --> 00:02:02,104 of objects and events in the world. 42 00:02:02,104 --> 00:02:05,454 Everything we know is based on these models. 43 00:02:05,454 --> 00:02:09,044 They never capture every detail of the things they describe, 44 00:02:09,044 --> 00:02:13,097 just enough for the brain to determine appropriate responses. 45 00:02:13,397 --> 00:02:16,877 For instance, one model built deep into the visual system 46 00:02:16,877 --> 00:02:20,137 codes white light as brightness without color. 47 00:02:20,137 --> 00:02:21,197 In reality, 48 00:02:21,197 --> 00:02:22,987 white light includes wavelengths 49 00:02:22,987 --> 00:02:26,337 that correspond to all the different colors we can see. 50 00:02:26,337 --> 00:02:30,027 Our perception of white light is wrong and oversimplified, 51 00:02:30,027 --> 00:02:32,487 but good enough for us to function. 52 00:02:32,487 --> 00:02:35,127 Likewise, the brain’s model of the physical body 53 00:02:35,127 --> 00:02:37,797 keeps track of the configuration of our limbs, 54 00:02:37,797 --> 00:02:40,987 but not of individual cells or even muscles, 55 00:02:40,987 --> 00:02:44,967 because that level of information isn’t needed to plan movement. 56 00:02:44,967 --> 00:02:48,707 If it didn’t have the model keeping track of the body’s size, shape, 57 00:02:48,707 --> 00:02:50,677 and how it is moving at any moment, 58 00:02:50,677 --> 00:02:53,087 we would quickly injure ourselves. 59 00:02:53,087 --> 00:02:55,797 The brain also needs models of itself. 60 00:02:55,797 --> 00:02:56,667 For example, 61 00:02:56,667 --> 00:03:01,187 the brain has the ability to pay attention to specific objects and events. 62 00:03:01,187 --> 00:03:03,358 It also controls that focus, 63 00:03:03,358 --> 00:03:05,268 shifting it from one thing to another, 64 00:03:05,268 --> 00:03:06,758 internal and external, 65 00:03:06,758 --> 00:03:08,368 according to our needs. 66 00:03:08,368 --> 00:03:10,578 Without the ability to direct our focus, 67 00:03:10,578 --> 00:03:15,318 we wouldn’t be able to assess threats, finish a meal, or function at all. 68 00:03:15,318 --> 00:03:17,497 To control focus effectively, 69 00:03:17,497 --> 00:03:20,907 the brain has to construct a model of its own attention. 70 00:03:20,907 --> 00:03:24,867 With 86 billion neurons constantly interacting with each other, 71 00:03:24,867 --> 00:03:28,657 there’s no way the brain’s model of its own information processing 72 00:03:28,657 --> 00:03:31,117 can be perfectly self-descriptive. 73 00:03:31,117 --> 00:03:32,787 But like the model of the body, 74 00:03:32,787 --> 00:03:34,897 or our conception of white light, 75 00:03:34,897 --> 00:03:36,527 it doesn’t have to be. 76 00:03:36,527 --> 00:03:40,337 Our certainty that we have a metaphysical, subjective experience 77 00:03:40,337 --> 00:03:42,647 may come from one of the brain’s models, 78 00:03:42,647 --> 00:03:46,377 a cut-corner description of what it means to process information 79 00:03:46,377 --> 00:03:49,197 in a focused and deep manner. 80 00:03:49,197 --> 00:03:51,867 Scientists have already begun trying to figure out 81 00:03:51,867 --> 00:03:54,787 how the brain creates that self model. 82 00:03:54,787 --> 00:03:59,517 MRI studies are a promising avenue for pinpointing the networks involved. 83 00:03:59,517 --> 00:04:02,497 These studies compare patterns of neural activation 84 00:04:02,497 --> 00:04:07,507 when someone is and isn’t conscious of a sensory stimulus, like an image. 85 00:04:07,507 --> 00:04:10,947 The results show that the areas needed for visual processing 86 00:04:10,947 --> 00:04:14,916 are activated whether or not the participant is aware of the image, 87 00:04:14,916 --> 00:04:17,677 but a whole additional network lights up 88 00:04:17,677 --> 00:04:21,387 only when they are conscious of seeing the image. 89 00:04:21,387 --> 00:04:24,237 Patients with hemispatial neglect, like P.S., 90 00:04:24,237 --> 00:04:28,467 typically have damage to one particular part of this network. 91 00:04:28,467 --> 00:04:32,789 More extensive damage to the network can sometimes lead to a vegetative state, 92 00:04:32,789 --> 00:04:35,719 with no sign of consciousness. 93 00:04:35,719 --> 00:04:38,499 Evidence like this brings us closer to understanding 94 00:04:38,499 --> 00:04:41,249 how consciousness is built into the brain, 95 00:04:41,249 --> 00:04:43,149 but there’s still much more to learn. 96 00:04:43,149 --> 00:04:44,009 For instance, 97 00:04:44,009 --> 00:04:46,859 the way neurons in the networks related to consciousness 98 00:04:46,859 --> 00:04:49,399 compute specific pieces of information 99 00:04:49,399 --> 00:04:52,369 is outside the scope of our current technology. 100 00:04:52,369 --> 00:04:55,449 As we approach questions of consciousness with science, 101 00:04:55,449 --> 00:04:58,979 we’ll open new lines of inquiry into human identity.