WEBVTT 00:00:06.817 --> 00:00:09.617 Imagine we want to build a new space port 00:00:09.617 --> 00:00:13.200 at one of four recently settled Martian bases, 00:00:13.200 --> 00:00:16.650 and are holding a vote to determine its location. 00:00:16.650 --> 00:00:23.482 Of the hundred colonists on Mars, 42 live on West Base, 26 on North Base, 00:00:23.482 --> 00:00:28.252 15 on South Base, and 17 on East Base. 00:00:28.252 --> 00:00:32.342 For our purposes, let’s assume that everyone prefers the space port 00:00:32.342 --> 00:00:37.155 to be as close to their base as possible, and will vote accordingly. 00:00:37.155 --> 00:00:40.445 What is the fairest way to conduct that vote? NOTE Paragraph 00:00:40.445 --> 00:00:44.400 The most straightforward solution would be to just let each individual 00:00:44.400 --> 00:00:48.750 cast a single ballot, and choose the location with the most votes. 00:00:48.750 --> 00:00:54.119 This is known as plurality voting, or "first past the post." 00:00:54.119 --> 00:00:57.179 In this case, West Base wins easily, 00:00:57.179 --> 00:00:59.791 since it has more residents than any other. 00:00:59.791 --> 00:01:04.031 And yet, most colonists would consider this the worst result, 00:01:04.031 --> 00:01:07.045 given how far it is from everyone else. 00:01:07.045 --> 00:01:12.099 So is plurality vote really the fairest method? NOTE Paragraph 00:01:12.099 --> 00:01:15.939 What if we tried a system like instant runoff voting, 00:01:15.939 --> 00:01:19.265 which accounts for the full range of people’s preferences 00:01:19.265 --> 00:01:21.591 rather than just their top choices? 00:01:21.591 --> 00:01:23.131 Here’s how it would work. 00:01:23.131 --> 00:01:27.001 First, voters rank each of the options from 1 to 4, 00:01:27.001 --> 00:01:29.651 and we compare their top picks. 00:01:29.651 --> 00:01:34.348 South receives the fewest votes for first place, so it’s eliminated. 00:01:34.348 --> 00:01:39.716 Its 15 votes get allocated to those voters’ second choice— 00:01:39.716 --> 00:01:43.666 East Base— giving it a total of 32. 00:01:43.666 --> 00:01:49.177 We then compare top preferences and cut the last place option again. 00:01:49.177 --> 00:01:51.357 This time North Base is eliminated. 00:01:51.357 --> 00:01:54.926 Its residents’ second choice would’ve been South Base, 00:01:54.926 --> 00:01:59.190 but since that’s already gone, the votes go to their third choice. 00:01:59.190 --> 00:02:05.390 That gives East 58 votes over West’s 42, making it the winner. 00:02:05.390 --> 00:02:08.090 But this doesn’t seem fair either. 00:02:08.090 --> 00:02:11.806 Not only did East start out in second-to-last place, 00:02:11.806 --> 00:02:16.280 but a majority ranked it among their two least preferred options. NOTE Paragraph 00:02:16.280 --> 00:02:20.867 Instead of using rankings, we could try voting in multiple rounds, 00:02:20.867 --> 00:02:25.057 with the top two winners proceeding to a separate runoff. 00:02:25.057 --> 00:02:29.120 Normally, this would mean West and North winning the first round, 00:02:29.120 --> 00:02:30.848 and North winning the second. 00:02:30.848 --> 00:02:33.509 But the residents of East Base realize 00:02:33.509 --> 00:02:36.029 that while they don’t have the votes to win, 00:02:36.029 --> 00:02:39.369 they can still skew the results in their favor. 00:02:39.369 --> 00:02:43.289 In the first round, they vote for South Base instead of their own, 00:02:43.289 --> 00:02:46.299 successfully keeping North from advancing. 00:02:46.299 --> 00:02:50.059 Thanks to this "tactical voting" by East Base residents, 00:02:50.059 --> 00:02:55.177 South wins the second round easily, despite being the least populated. 00:02:55.177 --> 00:02:59.762 Can a system be called fair and good if it incentivizes lying 00:02:59.762 --> 00:03:01.712 about your preferences? NOTE Paragraph 00:03:01.712 --> 00:03:05.511 Maybe what we need to do is let voters express a preference 00:03:05.511 --> 00:03:08.676 in every possible head-to-head matchup. 00:03:08.676 --> 00:03:11.671 This is known as the Condorcet method. 00:03:11.671 --> 00:03:15.203 Consider one matchup: West versus North. 00:03:15.203 --> 00:03:18.713 All 100 colonists vote on their preference between the two. 00:03:18.713 --> 00:03:23.516 So that's West's 42 versus the 58 from North, South, and East, 00:03:23.516 --> 00:03:25.731 who would all prefer North. 00:03:25.731 --> 00:03:29.066 Now do the same for the other five matchups. 00:03:29.066 --> 00:03:32.661 The victor will be whichever base wins the most times. 00:03:32.661 --> 00:03:36.622 Here, North wins three and South wins two. 00:03:36.622 --> 00:03:40.082 These are indeed the two most central locations, 00:03:40.082 --> 00:03:45.659 and North has the advantage of not being anyone’s least preferred choice. NOTE Paragraph 00:03:45.659 --> 00:03:50.846 So does that make the Condorcet method an ideal voting system in general? 00:03:50.846 --> 00:03:53.176 Not necessarily. 00:03:53.176 --> 00:03:55.877 Consider an election with three candidates. 00:03:55.877 --> 00:04:01.541 If voters prefer A over B, and B over C, but prefer C over A, 00:04:01.541 --> 00:04:04.151 this method fails to select a winner. NOTE Paragraph 00:04:04.151 --> 00:04:08.027 Over the decades, researchers and statisticians have come up with 00:04:08.027 --> 00:04:12.057 dozens of intricate ways of conducting and counting votes, 00:04:12.057 --> 00:04:14.840 and some have even been put into practice. 00:04:14.840 --> 00:04:16.737 But whichever one you choose, 00:04:16.737 --> 00:04:21.508 it's possible to imagine it delivering an unfair result. NOTE Paragraph 00:04:21.508 --> 00:04:25.128 It turns out that our intuitive concept of fairness 00:04:25.128 --> 00:04:29.590 actually contains a number of assumptions that may contradict each other. 00:04:29.590 --> 00:04:33.910 It doesn’t seem fair for some voters to have more influence than others. 00:04:33.910 --> 00:04:38.253 But nor does it seem fair to simply ignore minority preferences, 00:04:38.253 --> 00:04:41.419 or encourage people to game the system. 00:04:41.419 --> 00:04:45.453 In fact, mathematical proofs have shown that for any election 00:04:45.453 --> 00:04:47.243 with more than two options, 00:04:47.243 --> 00:04:51.023 it’s impossible to design a voting system that doesn’t violate 00:04:51.023 --> 00:04:55.513 at least some theoretically desirable criteria. 00:04:55.513 --> 00:05:00.030 So while we often think of democracy as a simple matter of counting votes, 00:05:00.030 --> 00:05:05.463 it’s also worth considering who benefits from the different ways of counting them.